ARISTÓTELES
(384 - 322 A.C)
Aristotle is a towering figure in ancient
Greek philosophy, making contributions to logic, metaphysics,
mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture,
medicine, dance and theatre. He was a student of Plato who in turn
studied under Socrates. He was more empirically-minded than Plato or Socrates
and is famous for rejecting Plato's theory of forms.
As a prolific writer and polymath, Aristotle radically
transformed most, if not all, areas of knowledge he touched. It is no wonder
that Aquinas referred to him simply as
"The Philosopher." In his lifetime, Aristotle wrote as many as 200
treatises, of which only 31 survive. Unfortunately for us, these works are in
the form of lecture notes and draft manuscripts never intended for general
readership, so they do not demonstrate his reputed polished prose style which
attracted many great followers, including the Roman Cicero. Aristotle was
the first to classify areas of human knowledge into distinct disciplines such
as mathematics, biology, and ethics. Some of these classifications are still
used today.
As the father of the field of logic, he was the first
to develop a formalized system for reasoning. Aristotle observed that the
validity of any argument can be determined by its structure rather than its
content. A classic example of a valid argument is his syllogism: All men are
mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore, Socrates is mortal. Given the structure
of this argument, as long as the premises are true, then the conclusion is also
guaranteed to be true. Aristotle’s brand of logic dominated this area of
thought until the rise of modern propositional logic and predicate
logic 2000 years later.
Aristotle’s emphasis on good reasoning combined with
his belief in the scientific method forms the backdrop for most of his work.
For example, in his work in ethics and politics, Aristotle identifies the
highest good with intellectual virtue; that is, a moral person is one who
cultivates certain virtues based on reasoning. And in his work on psychology
and the soul, Aristotle distinguishes sense perception from reason, which
unifies and interprets the sense perceptions and is the source of all
knowledge.
Aristotle famously rejected Plato’s theory of forms,
which states that properties such as beauty are abstract universal entities
that exist independent of the objects themselves. Instead, he argued that forms
are intrinsic to the objects
and cannot exist apart from them, and so must be studied in relation to them.
However, in discussing art, Aristotle seems to reject this, and instead argues
for idealized universal form which artists attempt to capture in their work.
Aristotle was the founder of the Lyceum, a school of
learning based in Athens, Greece; and he was an inspiration
for the Peripatetics, his followers from the
Lyceum.
Table of Contents
- Life
- Writings
- Logic
- Metaphysics
- Philosophy of Nature
- The Soul and Psychology
- Ethics
- Politics
- Art and Poetics
1. Life
Aristotle was born in 384 BCE at Stagirus, a now
extinct Greek colony and seaport on the coast of Thrace. His father Nichomachus was
court physician to King Amyntas of Macedonia, and from this began
Aristotle's long association with the Macedonian
Court, which considerably influenced his life.
While he was still a boy his father died. At age 17 his guardian, Proxenus,
sent him to Athens,
the intellectual center of the world, to complete his education. He joined the
Academy and studied under Plato, attending his lectures for
a period of twenty years. In the later years of his association with Plato and
the Academy he began to lecture on his own account, especially on the subject
of rhetoric. At the death of Plato in 347, the pre-eminent ability of Aristotle
would seem to have designated him to succeed to the leadership of the Academy.
But his divergence from Plato's teaching was too great to make this possible,
and Plato's nephew Speusippus was chosen instead. At the invitation of his
friend Hermeas, ruler of Atarneus and Assos in Mysia,
Aristotle left for his court. He stayed three year and, while there, married
Pythias, the niece of the King. In later life he was married a second time to a
woman named Herpyllis, who bore him a son, Nichomachus. At the end of three
years Hermeas was overtaken by the Persians, and Aristotle went to Mytilene. At
the invitation of Philip of Macedonia he became the tutor of his 13 year old
son Alexander (later world conqueror); he did this for the next five years.
Both Philip and Alexander appear to have paid Aristotle high honor, and there
were stories that Aristotle was supplied by the Macedonian court, not only with
funds for teaching, but also with thousands of slaves to collect specimens for
his studies in natural science. These stories are probably false and certainly
exaggerated.
Upon the death of Philip, Alexander succeeded to the
kingship and prepared for his subsequent conquests. Aristotle's work being
finished, he returned to Athens,
which he had not visited since the death of Plato. He found the Platonic school
flourishing under Xenocrates, and Platonism the dominant philosophy of Athens. He thus set up
his own school at a place called the Lyceum. When teaching at the
Lyceum, Aristotle had a habit of walking about as he discoursed. It was in
connection with this that his followers became known in later years as
the peripatetics, meaning
"to walk about." For the next thirteen years he devoted his energies
to his teaching and composing his philosophical treatises. He is said to have
given two kinds of lectures: the more detailed discussions in the morning for
an inner circle of advanced students, and the popular discourses in the evening
for the general body of lovers of knowledge. At the sudden death of Alexander
in 323 BCE., the pro-Macedonian government in Athens was overthrown, and a general reaction
occurred against anything Macedonian. A charge of impiety was trumped up
against him. To escape prosecution he fled to Chalcis
in Euboea so that (Aristotle says) "The
Athenians might not have another opportunity of sinning against philosophy as
they had already done in the person of Socrates." In the first year of his
residence at Chalcis
he complained of a stomach illness and died in 322 BCE.
2. Writings
It is reported that Aristotle's writings were held by
his student Theophrastus, who had succeeded Aristotle in leadership of the Peripatetic School. Theophrastus's library passed to
his pupil Neleus. To protect the books from theft, Neleus's heirs concealed
them in a vault, where they were damaged somewhat by dampness, moths and worms.
In this hiding place they were discovered about 100 BCE by Apellicon, a rich
book lover, and brought to Athens.
They were later taken to Rome after the capture
of Athens by
Sulla in 86 BCE. In Rome
they soon attracted the attention of scholars, and the new edition of them gave
fresh impetus to the study of Aristotle and of philosophy in general. This
collection is the basis of the works of Aristotle that we have today.
Strangely, the list of Aristotle's works given by Diogenes
Laertius does not contain any of these treatises. It is possible that Diogenes'
list is that of forgeries compiled at a time when the real works were lost to
sight.
The works of Aristotle fall under three headings: (1)
dialogues and other works of a popular character; (2) collections of facts and
material from scientific treatment; and (3) systematic works. Among his
writings of a popular nature the only one which we possess of any consequence
is the interesting tract On the Polity
of the Athenians. The works on the second group include 200 titles,
most in fragments, collected by Aristotle's school and used as research. Some
may have been done at the time of Aristotle's successor Theophrastus. Included
in this group are constitutions of 158 Greek states. The systematic treatises
of the third group are marked by a plainness of style, with none of the golden
flow of language which the ancients praised in Aristotle. This may be due to
the fact that these works were not, in most cases, published by Aristotle
himself or during his lifetime, but were edited after his death from unfinished
manuscripts. Until Werner Jaeger (1912) it was assumed that Aristotle's
writings presented a systematic account of his views. Jaeger argues for an early,
middle and late period (genetic approach), where the early period follows
Plato's theory of forms and soul, the middle rejects Plato, and the later
period (which includes most of his treatises) is more empirically oriented. Aristotle's systematic treatises may be grouped in
several divisions:
- Logic
- Categories (10 classifications of terms)
- On Interpretation (propositions, truth, modality)
- Prior Analytics (syllogistic logic)
- Posterior Analytics (scientific method and syllogism)
- Topics (rules for effective arguments and debate)
- On Sophistical Refutations (informal fallacies)
- Physical works
- Physics (explains change, motion, void, time)
- On the Heavens (structure of heaven, earth, elements)
- On Generation (through combining material constituents)
- Meteorologics (origin of comets, weather, disasters)
- Psychological works
- On the Soul (explains faculties, senses, mind, imagination)
- On Memory, Reminiscence, Dreams, and Prophesying
- Works on natural history
- History of Animals (physical/mental qualities, habits)
- On the parts of Animals
- On the Movement of Animals
- On the Progression of Animals
- On the Generation of Animals
- Minor treatises
- Problems
- Philosophical works
- Metaphysics (substance, cause, form, potentiality)
- Nicomachean Ethics (soul, happiness, virtue, friendship)
- Eudemain Ethics
- Magna Moralia
- Politics (best states, utopias, constitutions, revolutions)
- Rhetoric (elements of forensic and political debate)
- Poetics (tragedy, epic poetry)
3. Logic
Aristotle's writings on the general subject of logic
were grouped by the later Peripatetics under the name Organon, or instrument. From their
perspective, logic and reasoning was the chief preparatory instrument of
scientific investigation. Aristotle himself, however, uses the term
"logic" as equivalent to verbal reasoning. The Categories of Aristotle are
classifications of individual words (as opposed to sentences or propositions), and include the
following ten: substance, quantity, quality, relation, place, time, situation,
condition, action, passion. They seem to be arranged according to the order of
the questions we would ask in gaining knowledge of an object. For example, we
ask, first, what a thing is, then how great it is, next of what kind it is.
Substance is always regarded as the most important of these. Substances are
further divided into first and second: first substances are individual objects; second substances are
the species in which first
substances or individuals inhere.
Notions when isolated do not in themselves express
either truth or falsehood: it is only with the combination of ideas in a
proposition that truth and falsity are possible. The
elements of such a proposition are the noun substantive and the verb. The
combination of words gives rise to rational speech and thought, conveys a
meaning both in its parts and as a whole. Such thought may take many forms, but
logic considers only demonstrative
forms which express truth and falsehood. The truth or falsity of propositions
is determined by their agreement or disagreement with the facts they represent.
Thus propositions are either affirmative or negative, each of which again may
be either universal or particular or undesignated. A definition, for Aristotle
is a statement of the essential character of a subject, and involves both the
genus and the difference. To get at a true definition we must find out those
qualities within the genus which taken separately are wider than the subject to
be defined, but taken together are precisely equal to it. For example,
"prime," "odd," and "number" are each wider than
"triplet" (that is, a collection of any three items, such as three
rocks); but taken together they are just equal to it. The genus definition must
be formed so that no species is left out. Having determined the genus and
species, we must next find the points of similarity in the species separately
and then consider the common characteristics of different species. Definitions
may be imperfect by (1) being obscure, (2) by being too wide, or (3) by not
stating the essential and fundamental attributes. Obscurity may arise from the
use of equivocal expressions, of metaphorical phrases, or of eccentric words.
The heart of Aristotle's logic is the syllogism, the classic example of which
is as follows: All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore, Socrates is
mortal. The syllogistic form of logical argumentation dominated logic for 2,000
years until the rise of modern propositional and predicate logic thanks to Frege,
Russell, and others.
4. Metaphysics
Aristotle's editors gave the name
"Metaphysics" to his works on first
philosophy, either because they went beyond or followed after his physical investigations.
Aristotle begins by sketching the history of philosophy. For Aristotle,
philosophy arose historically after basic necessities were secured. It grew out
of a feeling of curiosity and wonder, to which religious myth gave only
provisional satisfaction. The earliest speculators (i.e. Thales, Anaximenes,
Anaximander) were philosophers of nature. The Pythagoreans succeeded these with
mathematical abstractions. The level of pure thought was reached partly in the
Eleatic philosophers (such as Parmenides) and Anaxagoras, but more completely
in the work of Socrates. Socrates' contribution was the expression of general
conceptions in the form of definitions, which he arrived at by induction and
analogy. For Aristotle, the subject of metaphysics deals with the first
principles of scientific knowledge and the ultimate conditions of all
existence. More specifically, it deals with existence in its most fundamental
state (i.e. being as
being), and the essential attributes of existence. This can be contrasted with
mathematics which deals with existence in terms of lines or angles, and not
existence as it is in itself. In its universal character, metaphysics
superficially resembles dialectics and sophistry. However, it differs from
dialectics which is tentative, and it differs from sophistry which is a
pretence of knowledge without the reality.
The axioms of science fall under the consideration of
the metaphysician insofar as they are properties ofall existence. Aristotle argues that there are a handful of
universal truths. Against the followers of Heraclitus and Protagoras, Aristotle
defends both the laws of contradiction, and that of excluded middle. He does
this by showing that their denial is suicidal. Carried out to its logical
consequences, the denial of these laws would lead to the sameness of all facts
and all assertions. It would also result in an indifference in conduct. As the
science of being as being,
the leading question of Aristotle's metaphysics is, What is meant by the real
or true substance? Plato tried to solve the same question by positing a
universal and invariable element of knowledge and existence -- the forms -- as
the only real permanent besides the changing phenomena of the senses. Aristotle
attacks Plato's theory of the forms on three different grounds.
First, Aristotle argues, forms are powerless to
explain changes of things
and a thing's ultimate extinction. Forms are not causes of movement and
alteration in the physical objects of sensation. Second, forms are equally incompetent to
explain how we arrive at knowledge
of particular things. For, to have knowledge of a particular object, it must be
knowledge of the substance which is in
that things. However, the forms place knowledge outside of particular things.
Further, to suppose that we know particular things better by adding on their
general conceptions of their forms, is about as absurd as to imagine that we
can count numbers better by multiplying them. Finally, if forms were needed to
explain our knowledge of particular objects, then forms must be used to explain
our knowledge of objects of art; however, Platonists do not recognize such
forms. The third ground of
attack is that the forms simply cannot explain the existence of particular objects. Plato
contends that forms do not exist in
the particular objects which partake in the forms. However, that substance of a
particular thing cannot be separated from the thing itself. Further, aside from
the jargon of "participation," Plato does not explain the relation
between forms and particular things. In reality, it is merely metaphorical to
describe the forms as patterns of things; for, what is a genus to one object is
a species to a higher class, the same idea will have to be both a form and a
particular thing at the same time. Finally, on Plato's account of the forms, we
must imagine an intermediate link between the form and the particular object,
and so on ad infinitum:
there must always be a "third man" between the individual man and the
form of man.
For Aristotle, the form is not something outside the
object, but rather in the
varied phenomena of sense. Real substance, or true being, is not the abstract
form, but rather the concrete
individual thing. Unfortunately, Aristotle's theory of substance is not
altogether consistent with itself. In the Categories the notion of substance tends to be nominalistic
(that is, substance is a concept we apply to things). In theMetaphysics, though, it frequently
inclines towards realism (that is, substance has a real existence in itself).
We are also struck by the apparent contradiction in his claims that science
deals with universal concepts, and substance is declared to be an individual.
In any case, substance is for him a merging of matter into form. The term
"matter" is used by Aristotle in four overlapping senses. First, it is the underlying structure of
changes, particularly changes of growth and of decay. Secondly, it is the potential which has
implicitly the capacity to develop into reality. Thirdly, it is a kind of stuff without
specific qualities and so is indeterminate and contingent. Fourthly, it is identical with form when
it takes on a form in its actualized and final phase.
The development of potentiality to actuality is one of
the most important aspects of Aristotle's philosophy. It was intended to solve
the difficulties which earlier thinkers had raised with reference to the
beginnings of existence and the relations of the one and many. The actual vs.
potential state of things is explained in terms of the causes which act on
things. There are four causes:
- Material cause, or the elements out of which an object is created;
- Efficient cause, or the means by which it is created;
- Formal cause, or the expression of what it is;
- Final cause, or the end for which it is.
Take, for example, a bronze statue. Its material cause
is the bronze itself. Its efficient cause is the sculptor, insofar has he
forces the bronze into shape. The formal cause is the idea of the completed
statue. The final cause is the idea of the statue as it prompts the sculptor to act on the
bronze. The final cause tends to be the same as the formal cause, and both of
these can be subsumed by the efficient cause. Of the four, it is the formal and
final which is the most important, and which most truly gives the explanation
of an object. The final end (purpose, or teleology) of a thing is realized in
the full perfection of the object itself, not in our conception of it. Final
cause is thus internal to the nature of the object itself, and not something we
subjectively impose on it.
To Aristotle, God is the first of all
substances, the necessary first source of movement who is himself unmoved. God
is a being with everlasting life, and perfect blessedness, engaged in
never-ending contemplation.
5. Philosophy of Nature
Aristotle sees the universe as a scale lying between
the two extremes: form without matter is on one end, and matter without form is
on the other end. The passage of matter into form must be shown in its various
stages in the world of nature. To do this is the object of Aristotle's physics,
or philosophy of nature. It is important to keep in mind that the passage from
form to matter within nature is a movement towards ends or purposes. Everything
in nature has its end and function, and nothing is without its purpose.
Everywhere we find evidences of design and rational plan. No doctrine of
physics can ignore the fundamental notions of motion, space, and time. Motion
is the passage of matter into form, and it is of four kinds: (1) motion which
affects the substance of a thing, particularly its beginning and its ending;
(2) motion which brings about changes in quality; (3) motion which brings about
changes in quantity, by increasing it and decreasing it; and (4) motion which
brings about locomotion, or change of place. Of these the last is the most
fundamental and important.
Aristotle rejects the definition of space as the void.
Empty space is an impossibility. Hence, too, he disagrees with the view of
Plato and the Pythagoreans that the elements are composed of geometrical
figures. Space is defined as the limit of the surrounding body towards what is
surrounded. Time is defined as the measure of
motion in regard to what is earlier and later. It thus depends for its
existence upon motion. If there where no change in the universe, there would be
no time. Since it is the measuring or counting of motion, it also depends for
its existence on a counting mind. If there were no mind to count, there could
be no time. As to the infinite divisibility of space and time, and the
paradoxes proposed byZeno, Aristotle argues that space
and time are potentially divisible ad
infinitum, but are not actually so divided.
After these preliminaries, Aristotle passes to the
main subject of physics, the scale of being. The first thing to notice about
this scale is that it is a scale of values. What is higher on the scale of
being is of more worth, because the principle of form is more advanced in it.
Species on this scale are eternally fixed in their place, and cannot evolve
over time. The higher items on the scale are also more organized. Further, the
lower items are inorganic and the higher are organic. The principle which gives
internal organization to the higher or organic items on the scale of being is
life, or what he calls the soul of the organism. Even the human soul is nothing
but the organization of the body. Plants are the lowest forms of life on the
scale, and their souls contain a nutritive element by which it preserves
itself. Animals are above plants on the scale, and their souls contain an appetitive
feature which allows them to have sensations, desires, and thus gives them the
ability to move. The scale of being proceeds from animals to humans. The human
soul shares the nutritive element with plants, and the appetitive element with
animals, but also has a rational element which is distinctively our own. The
details of the appetitive and rational aspects of the soul are described in the
following two sections.
6. The Soul and Psychology
Soul is defined by Aristotle as the perfect
expression or realization of a natural body. From this definition it follows
that there is a close connection between psychological states, and
physiological processes. Body and soul are unified in the same way that wax and
an impression stamped on it are unified. Metaphysicians before Aristotle
discussed the soul abstractly without any regard to the bodily environment; this,
Aristotle believes, was a mistake. At the same time, Aristotle regards the soul
or mind not as the product of the physiological conditions of the body, but as
the truth of the body --
the substance in which only the bodily conditions gain their real meaning.
The soul manifests its activity in certain
"faculties" or "parts" which correspond with the stages of
biological development, and are the faculties of nutrition (peculiar to
plants), that of movement (peculiar to animals), and that of reason (peculiar
to humans). These faculties resemble mathematical figures in which the higher
includes the lower, and must be understood not as like actual physical parts,
but like suchaspects as convex
and concave which we distinguish in the same line. The mind remains throughout
a unity: and it is absurd to speak of it, as Plato did, as desiring with one
part and feeling anger with another. Sense perception is a faculty of receiving
the forms of outward objects independently of the matter of which they are
composed, just as the wax takes on the figure of the seal without the gold or
other metal of which the seal is composed. As the subject of impression,
perception involves a movement and a kind of qualitative change; but perception
is not merely a passive or receptive affection. It in turn acts, and,distinguishing between the qualities of
outward things, becomes "a movement of the soul through the medium of the
body."
The objects of the senses may be either (1) special,
(such as color is the special object of sight, and sound of hearing), (2)
common, or apprehended by several senses in combination (such as motion or
figure), or (3) incidental or inferential (such as when from the immediate
sensation of white we come to know a person or object which is white). There are five special senses. Of
these, touch is the must rudimentary, hearing the most instructive, and sight
the most ennobling. The organ in these senses never acts directly , but is
affected by some medium such as air. Even touch, which seems to act by actual contact,
probably involves some vehicle of communication. For Aristotle, the heart is
the common or central sense organ. It recognizes the common qualities which are
involved in all particular objects of sensation. It is, first, the sense which
brings us a consciousness of sensation. Secondly, in one act before the mind,
it holds up the objects of our knowledge and enables us to distinguish between
the reports of different senses.
Aristotle defines the imagination as "the
movement which results upon an actual sensation." In other words, it is
the process by which an impression of the senses is pictured and retained
before the mind, and is accordingly the basis of memory. The representative
pictures which it provides form the materials of reason. Illusions and dreams
are both alike due to an excitement in the organ of sense similar to that which
would be caused by the actual presence of the sensible phenomenon. Memory is
defined as the permanent possession of the sensuous picture as a copy which
represents the object of which it is a picture. Recollection, or the calling
back to mind the residue of memory, depends on the laws which regulate the
association of our ideas. We trace the associations by starting with the
thought of the object present to us, then considering what is similar, contrary
or contiguous.
Reason is the source of the first principles of
knowledge. Reason is opposed to the sense insofar as sensations are restricted
and individual, and thought is free and universal. Also, while the senses deals
with the concrete and material aspect of phenomena, reason deals with the
abstract and ideal aspects. But while reason is in itself the source of general
ideas, it is so only potentially. For, it arrives at them only by a process of
development in which it gradually clothes sense in thought, and unifies and
interprets sense-presentations. This work of reason in thinking beings suggests
the question: How can immaterial thought come to receive material things? It is
only possible in virtue of some community
between thought and things. Aristotle recognizes an active reason which makes objects of thought. This is
distinguished from passive reason which receives, combines and compares the
objects of thought. Active reason makes the world intelligible, and bestows on
the materials of knowledge those ideas or categories which make them accessible
to thought. This is just as the sun communicates to material objects that
light, without which color would be invisible, and sight would have no object.
Hence reason is the constant support of an intelligible world. While assigning
reason to the soul of humans, Aristotle describes it as coming from without,
and almost seems to identify it with God as the eternal and omnipresent
thinker. Even in humans, in short, reason realizes something of the essential
characteristic of absolute thought -- the unity of thought as subject with
thought as object.
7. Ethics
Ethics, as viewed by Aristotle, is an attempt to find
out our chief end or highest good: an end which he maintains is really final.
Though many ends of life are only means to further ends, our aspirations and
desires must have some final object or pursuit. Such a chief end is universally
called happiness. But people mean such different things by the expression that
he finds it necessary to discuss the nature of it for himself. For starters,
happiness must be based on human nature, and must begin from the facts of
personal experience. Thus, happiness cannot be found in any abstract or ideal
notion, like Plato's self-existing good. It must be something practical and
human. It must then be found in the work and life which is unique to humans.
But this is neither the vegetative life we share with plants nor the sensitive
existence which we share with animals. It follows therefore that true happiness
lies in the active life of a rational being or in a perfect realization and
outworking of the true soul and self, continued throughout a lifetime.
Aristotle expands his notion of happiness through an
analysis of the human soul which structures and animates a living human
organism. The parts of the soul are
divided as follows:
|
Calculative -- Intellectual Virtue
|
Rational
|
|
|
Appetitive -- Moral Virtue
|
Irrational
|
|
|
Vegetative -- Nutritional Virtue
|
The human soul has an irrational element which is
shared with the animals, and a rational element which is distinctly human. The
most primitive irrational element is the vegetative faculty which is
responsible for nutrition and growth. An organism which does this well may be
said to have a nutritional virtue. The second tier of the soul is the
appetitive faculty which is responsible for our emotions and desires (such as
joy, grief, hope and fear). This faculty is both rational and irrational. It is
irrational since even animals experience desires. However, it is also rational
since humans have the distinct ability to control these desires with the help
of reason. The human ability to properly control these desires is called moral
virtue, and is the focus of morality. Aristotle notes that there is a purely
rational part of the soul, the calculative, which is responsible for the human
ability to contemplate, reason logically, and formulate scientific principles.
The mastery of these abilities is called intellectual virtue.
Aristotle continues by making several general points
about the nature of moral virtues (i.e. desire-regulating virtues). First, he
argues that the ability to regulate our desires is not instinctive, but learned
and is the outcome of both teaching and practice. Second, he notes that if we
regulate our desires either too much or too little, then we create problems. As
an analogy, Aristotle comments that, either "excess or deficiency of
gymnastic exercise is fatal to strength." Third, he argues that
desire-regulating virtues are character traits, and are not to be understood as
either emotions or mental faculties.
The core of Aristotle's account of moral virtue is his
doctrine of the mean. According to this doctrine, moral virtues are
desire-regulating character traits which are at a mean between more extreme
character traits (or vices). For example, in response to the natural emotion of
fear, we should develop the virtuous character trait of courage. If we develop
an excessive character trait by curbing fear too much, then we are said to be
rash, which is a vice. If, on the other extreme, we develop a deficient
character trait by curbing fear too little, then we are said to be cowardly,
which is also a vice. The virtue of courage, then, lies at the mean between the
excessive extreme of rashness, and the deficient extreme of cowardice.
Aristotle is quick to point out that the virtuous mean is not a strict
mathematical mean between two extremes. For example, if eating 100 apples is
too many, and eating zero apples is too little, this does not imply that we
should eat 50 apples, which is the mathematical mean. Instead, the mean is
rationally determined, based on the relative merits of the situation. That is,
it is "as a prudent man would determine it." He concludes that it is
difficult to live the virtuous life primarily because it is often difficult to
find the mean between the extremes.
Most moral virtues, and not just courage, are to be
understood as falling at the mean between two accompanying vices. His list may be represented by the following table:
Vice of Deficiency
|
Virtuous Mean
|
Vice of Excess
|
Cowardice
|
Courage
|
Rashness
|
Insensibility
|
Temperance
|
Intemperance
|
Illiberality
|
Liberality
|
Prodigality
|
Pettiness
|
Munificence
|
Vulgarity
|
Humble-mindedness
|
High-mindedness
|
Vaingloriness
|
Want
of Ambition
|
Right
Ambition
|
Over-ambition
|
Spiritlessness
|
Good
Temper
|
Irascibility
|
Surliness
|
Friendly
Civility
|
Obsequiousness
|
Ironical
Depreciation
|
Sincerity
|
Boastfulness
|
Boorishness
|
Wittiness
|
Buffoonery
|
Shamelessness
|
Modesty
|
Bashfulness
|
Callousness
|
Just
Resentment
|
Spitefulness
|
The prominent virtue of this list is high-mindedness,
which, as being a kind of ideal self-respect, is regarded as the crown of all
the other virtues, depending on them for its existence, and itself in turn
tending to intensify their force. The list seems to be more a deduction from
the formula than a statement of the facts on which the formula itself depends,
and Aristotle accordingly finds language frequently inadequate to express the
states of excess or defect which his theory involves (for example in dealing
with the virtue of ambition). Throughout the list he insists on the
"autonomy of will" as indispensable to virtue: courage for instance
is only really worthy of the name when done from a love of honor and duty: munificence
again becomes vulgarity when it is not exercised from a love of what is right
and beautiful, but for displaying wealth.
Justice is used both in a general and in a special
sense. In its general sense it is equivalent to the observance of law. As such
it is the same thing as virtue, differing only insofar as virtue exercises the
disposition simply in the abstract, and justice applies it in dealings with
people. Particular justice displays itself in two forms. First, distributive justice hands out honors and
rewards according to the merits of the recipients. Second, corrective justice takes no account of
the position of the parties concerned, but simply secures equality between the
two by taking away from the advantage of the one and adding it to the
disadvantage of the other. Strictly speaking, distributive and corrective
justice are more than mere retaliation and reciprocity. However, in concrete
situations of civil life, retaliation and reciprocity is an adequate formula
since such circumstances involve money, depending on a relation between
producer and consumer. Since absolute justice is abstract in nature, in the
real world it must be supplemented with equity, which corrects and modifies the
laws of justice where it falls short. Thus, morality requires a standard which
will not only regulate the inadequacies of absolute justice but be also an idea
of moral progress.
This idea of morality is given by the faculty of moral
insight. The truly good person is at the same time a person of perfect insight,
and a person of perfect insight is also perfectly good. Our idea of the
ultimate end of moral action is developed through habitual experience, and this
gradually frames itself out of particular perceptions. It is the job of reason
to apprehend and organize these particular perceptions. However, moral action
is never the result of a mere act of the understanding, nor is it the result of
a simple desire which views objects merely as things which produce pain or
pleasure. We start with a rational conception of what is advantageous, but this
conception is in itself powerless without the natural impulse which will give
it strength. The will or purpose implied by morality is thus either reason
stimulated to act by desire, or desire guided and controlled by understanding.
These factors then motivate the willful action. Freedom of the will is a factor
with both virtuous choices and vicious choices. Actions are involuntary only
when another person forces our action, or if we are ignorant of important
details in actions. Actions are voluntary when the originating cause of action
(either virtuous or vicious) lies in ourselves.
Moral weakness of the will results in someone does
what is wrong, knowing that it is right, and yet follows his desire against
reason. For Aristotle, this condition is not a myth, as Socrates supposed it
was. The problem is a matter of conflicting moral principles. Moral action may
be represented as a syllogism in which a general principle of morality forms
the first (i.e. major) premise, while the particular application is the second
(i.e. minor) premise. The conclusion, though, which is arrived at through
speculation, is not always carried out in practice. The moral syllogism is not
simply a matter of logic, but involves psychological drives and desires. Desires
can lead to a minor premise being applied to one rather than another of two
major premises existing in the agent's mind. Animals, on the other hand, cannot
be called weak willed or incontinent since such a conflict of principles is not
possible with them.
Pleasure is not to be identified with Good. Pleasure
is found in the consciousness of free spontaneous action. It is an invisible
experience, like vision, and is always present when a perfect organ acts upon a
perfect object. Pleasures accordingly differ in kind, varying along with the
different value of the functions of which they are the expression. They are
determined ultimately by the judgment of "the good person." Our chief
end is the perfect development of our true nature; it thus must be particularly
found in the realization of our highest faculty, that is, reason. It is this in
fact which constitutes our personality, and we would not be pursuing our own
life, but the life of some lower being, if we followed any other aim. Self-love
accordingly may be said to be the highest law of morals, because while such
self-love may be understood as the selfishness which gratifies a person's lower
nature, it may also be, and is rightly, the love of that higher and rational
nature which constitutes each person's true self. Such a life of thought is
further recommended as that which is most pleasant, most self-sufficient, most
continuous, and most consonant with our purpose. It is also that which is most
akin to the life of God: for God cannot be conceived as practising the ordinary
moral virtues and must therefore find his happiness in contemplation.
Friendship is an indispensable aid in framing for
ourselves the higher moral life; if not itself a virtue, it is at least
associated with virtue, and it proves itself of service in almost all
conditions of our existence. Such results, however, are to be derived not from
the worldly friendships of utility or pleasure, but only from those which are
founded on virtue. The true friend is in fact a second self, and the true moral
value of friendship lies in the fact that the friend presents to us a mirror of
good actions, and so intensifies our consciousness and our appreciation of
life.
8. Politics
Aristotle does not regard politics as a separate
science from ethics, but as the completion, and almost a verification of it.
The moral ideal in political administration is only a different aspect of that
which also applies to individual happiness. Humans are by nature social beings,
and the possession of rational speech (logos) in itself leads us to social
union. The state is a development from the family through the village
community, an offshoot of the family. Formed originally for the satisfaction of
natural wants, it exists afterwards for moral ends and for the promotion of the
higher life. The state in fact is no mere local union for the prevention of
wrong doing, and the convenience of exchange. It is also no mere institution
for the protection of goods and property. It is a genuine moral organization
for advancing the development of humans.
The family, which is chronologically prior to the
state, involves a series of relations between husband and wife, parent and
child, master and slave. Aristotle regards the slave as a piece of live
property having no existence except in relation to his master. Slavery is a
natural institution because there is a ruling and a subject class among people
related to each other as soul to body; however, we must distinguish between
those who are slaves by nature, and those who have become slaves merely by war
and conquest. Household management involves the acquisition of riches, but must
be distinguished from money-making for its own sake. Wealth is everything whose
value can be measured by money; but it is the use rather than the possession of
commodities which constitutes riches.
Financial exchange first involved bartering. However,
with the difficulties of transmission between countries widely separated from
each other, money as a currency arose. At first it was merely a specific amount
of weighted or measured metal. Afterwards it received a stamp to mark the
amount. Demand is the real standard of value. Currency, therefore, is merely a
convention which represents the demand; it stands between the producer and the
recipient and secures fairness. Usury is an unnatural and reprehensible use of
money.
The communal ownership of wives and property as
sketched by Plato in the Republic
rests on a false conception of political society. For, the state is not a
homogeneous unity, as Plato believed, but rather is made up of dissimilar
elements. The classification of constitutions is based on the fact that
government may be exercised either for the good of the governed or of the
governing, and may be either concentrated in one person or shared by a few or
by the many. There are thus three true forms of government: monarchy,
aristocracy, and constitutional republic. The perverted forms of these are
tyranny, oligarchy and democracy. The difference between the last two is not
that democracy is a government of the many, and oligarchy of the few; instead,
democracy is the state of the poor, and oligarchy of the rich. Considered in
the abstract, these six states stand in the following order of preference:
monarchy, aristocracy, constitutional republic, democracy, oligarchy, tyranny.
But though with a perfect person monarchy would be the highest form of
government, the absence of such people puts it practically out of
consideration. Similarly, true aristocracy is hardly ever found in its
uncorrupted form. It is in the constitution that the good person and the good
citizen coincide. Ideal preferences aside, then, the constitutional republic is
regarded as the best attainable
form of government, especially as it secures that predominance of a large
middle class, which is the chief basis of permanence in any state. With the
spread of population, democracy is likely to become the general form of
government.
Which is the best state is a question that cannot be
directly answered. Different races are suited for different forms of
government, and the question which meets the politician is not so much what is
abstractly the best state, but what is the best state under existing
circumstances. Generally, however, the best state will enable anyone to act in
the best and live in the happiest manner. To serve this end the ideal state
should be neither too great nor too small, but simply self-sufficient. It
should occupy a favorable position towards land and sea and consist of citizens
gifted with the spirit of the northern nations, and the intelligence of the
Asiatic nations. It should further take particular care to exclude from
government all those engaged in trade and commerce; "the best state will
not make the "working man" a citizen; it should provide support
religious worship; it should secure morality through the educational influences
of law and early training. Law, for Aristotle, is the outward expression of the
moral ideal without the bias of human feeling. It is thus no mere agreement or
convention, but a moral force coextensive with all virtue. Since it is
universal in its character, it requires modification and adaptation to
particular circumstances through equity.
Education should be guided by legislation to make it
correspond with the results of psychological analysis, and follow the gradual
development of the bodily and mental faculties. Children should during their
earliest years be carefully protected from all injurious associations, and be
introduced to such amusements as will prepare them for the serious duties of
life. Their literary education should begin in their seventh year, and continue
to their twenty-first year. This period is divided into two courses of
training, one from age seven to puberty, and the other from puberty to age
twenty-one. Such education should not be left to private enterprise, but should
be undertaken by the state. There are four main branches of education: reading
and writing, Gymnastics, music, and painting. They should not be studied to
achieve a specific aim, but in the liberal spirit which creates true freemen.
Thus, for example, gymnastics should not be pursued by itself exclusively, or
it will result in a harsh savage type of character. Painting must not be
studied merely to prevent people from being cheated in pictures, but to make
them attend to physical beauty. Music must not be studied merely for amusement,
but for the moral influence which it exerts on the feelings. Indeed all true
education is, as Plato saw, a training of our sympathies so that we may love
and hate in a right manner.
9. Art and Poetics
Art is defined by Aristotle as the realization in
external form of a true idea, and is traced back to that natural love of
imitation which characterizes humans, and to the pleasure which we feel in
recognizing likenesses. Art however is not limited to mere copying. It
idealizes nature and completes its deficiencies: it seeks to grasp the
universal type in the individual phenomenon. The distinction therefore between
poetic art and history is not that the one uses meter, and the other does not. The
distinction is that while history is limited to what has actually happened,
poetry depicts things in their universal character. And, therefore,
"poetry is more philosophical and more elevated than history." Such
imitation may represent people either as better or as worse than people usually
are, or it may neither go beyond nor fall below the average standard. Comedy is
the imitation of the worse examples of humanity, understood however not in the
sense of absolute badness, but only in so far as what is low and ignoble enters
into what is laughable and comic.
Tragedy, on the other hand, is the representation of a
serious or meaningful, rounded or finished, and more or less extended or
far-reaching action -- a representation which is effected by action and not
mere narration. It is fitted by portraying events which excite fear and pity in
the mind of the observer to purify or purge these feelings and extend and
regulate their sympathy. It is thus a homeopathic curing of the passions.
Insofar as art in general universalizes particular events, tragedy, in
depicting passionate and critical situations, takes the observer outside the
selfish and individual standpoint, and views them in connection with the
general lot of human beings. This is similar to Aristotle's explanation of the
use of orgiastic music in the worship of Bacchas and other deities: it affords
an outlet for religious fervor and thus steadies one's religious sentiments.
Author Information
The author of this article is anonymous. The IEP is
actively seeking an author who will write a replacement article.
Aristotle: Biology
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.) may be
said to be the first biologist in the Western tradition. Though there are
physicians and other natural philosophers who remark on various flora and fauna
before Aristotle, none of them brings to his study a systematic critical
empiricism. Aristotle’s biological science is important to understand, not only
because it gives us a view into the history and philosophy of science, but also
because it allows us more deeply to understand his non-biological works, since
certain key concepts from Aristotle’s biology repeat themselves in his other
writings. Since a significant portion of the corpus of Aristotle’s work is on
biology, it is natural to expect his work in biology to resonate in his other
writings. One may, for example, use concepts from the biological works to
better understand the ethics or metaphysics of Aristotle.
This article will begin with a brief explanation of
his biological views and move toward several key explanatory concepts that
Aristotle employs. These concepts are essential because they stand as
candidates for a philosophy of biology. If Aristotle’s principles are
insightful, then he has gone a long way towards creating the first systematic
and critical system of biological thought. It is for this reason (rather than
the particular observations themselves) that moderns are interested in
Aristotle’s biological writings.
Table of Contents
- His Life
- The Scope of Aristotle’s Biological Works
- The Specialist and the Generalist
- The Two Modes of Causal Explanation
- Aristotle’s Theory of Soul
- The Biological Practice: Outlines of a Systematics
- “The more and the less” and “Epi to polu”
- Significant Achievements and Mistakes
- Conclusion
- References and Further Reading
1. His Life
Aristotle was born in the year 384 B.C. in the town of
Stagira (the modern town Stavros), a coastal Macedonian town to the north of
Greece. He was raised at the court of Amyntas where he probably met and was
friends with Philip (later to become king and father to Alexander, the Great).
When Aristotle was around 18, he was sent to Athens to study in Plato’s
Academy. Aristotle spent twenty years at the Academy until Plato’s death,
although Diogenes says Aristotle left before Plato’s death. When Plato was
succeeded by his nephew, Speusippus, as head of the Academy, Aristotle accepted
an invitation to join a former student, Hermeias, who was gathering a Platonic
circle about him in Assos in Mysia (near Troy). Aristotle spent three years in
this environment. During this time, he may have done some of the natural
investigations that later became The
History of Animals.
At the end of Aristotle’s stay in Mysia, he moved to
Lesbos (an adjacent island). This move may have been prompted by Theophrastus,
a fellow of the Academy who was much influenced by Aristotle. It is probable
(according to D’Arcy Thompson) that Aristotle performed some important
biological investigations during this period.
Aristotle returned to Athens (circa 334-5). This began
a period of great productivity. He rented some grounds in woods sacred to
Apollo. It was here that Aristotle set-up his school (Diog. Laert V, 51).
At his school Aristotle also accumulated a large
number of manuscripts and created a library that was a model for later libraries
in Alexandria and Pergamon. According to one tradition, Alexander (his former
pupil) paid him a handsome sum of money each year as a form of gratitude (as
well as some exotic animals for Aristotle to study that Alexander encountered
in his conquests).
At the death of Alexander in 323, Athens once again
was full of anti-Macedonian sentiment. A charge of impiety was brought against
Aristotle due to a poem he had written for Hermeias. One martyr for philosophy
(Socrates) was enough for Aristotle and so he left his school to his colleague,
Theophrastus, and fled to the Macedonian Chalcis. Here in 322 he died of a
disease that is still the subject of speculation.
2. The Scope of Aristotle’s Biological Works
There is some dispute as to which works should be
classified as the biological works of Aristotle. This is indeed a contentious
question that is especially difficult for a systematic philosopher such as
Aristotle. Generally speaking, a systematic philosopher is one who constructs
various philosophical distinctions that, in turn, can be applied to a number of
different contexts. Thus, a distinction such as “the more and the less” that
has its roots in biology explaining that certain animal parts are greater
(bigger) among some individuals and smaller among others, can also be used in
the ethics as a cornerstone of the doctrine of the mean as a criterion for
virtue. That is, one varies from the mean by the principle of the more and the
less. For example, if courage is the mean, then the defect of excess would be
“foolhardiness” while the defect of paucity would be “cowardice.” The boundary
between what we’d consider “biology” proper vs. what we’d think of as
psychology, philosophy of mind, and metaphysics is often hard to draw in
Aristotle. That’s because Aristotle’s understanding of biology informs his
metaphysics and philosophy of mind, but likewise, he often uses the
distinctions drawn in his metaphysics in order to deal with biological issues.
In this article, the biological works are: (a) works
that deal specifically with biological topics such as: The Parts of Animals (PA), The Generation of Animals
(GA), The History of Animals (HA), The Movement of Animals, The Progression of
Animals, On Sense and Sensible Objects, On Memory and Recollection, On Sleep and
Waking, On Dreams, On Prophecy in Sleep, On Length and Shortness of Life, On
Youth and Old Age, On Life and Death, On Respiration, On Breath, and On Plants, and (b) the work that deals with psuche (soul), On the Soul—though this work deals with
metaphysical issues very explicitly, as well. This list does not include works
such as the Metaphysics, Physics,
Posterior Analytics, Categories, Nicomachean Ethics, or The Politics even though they contain
many arguments that are augmented by an understanding of Aristotle’s biological
science. Nor does this article examine any of the reputedly lost works (listed
by ancient authors but not existing today) such as Dissections, On Composite Animals, On Sterility, On
Physiognomy, and On
Medicine . Some of these titles may have sections that have
survived in part within the present corpus, but this is doubtful.
3. The Specialist and the Generalist
The distinction between the specialist and the
generalist is a good starting point for understanding Aristotle’s philosophy of
biology. The specialist is one who has a considerable body of experience in
practical fieldwork while the generalist is one who knows many different areas
of study. This distinction is brought out in Book One of the Parts of Animals (PA). At PA 639a 1-7
Aristotle says,
In all study and investigation, be it exalted or
mundane, there appear to be two types of proficiency: one is that of exact,
scientific knowledge while the other is a generalist’s understanding. (my tr.)
Aristotle does not mean to denigrate or to exalt
either. Both are necessary for natural investigations. The generalist’s
understanding is holistic and puts some area of study into a proper genus,
while scientific knowledge deals with causes and definitions at the level of
the species. These two skills are demonstrated by the following example:
An example of what I mean is the question of whether
one should take a single species and state its differentia independently, for
example, homo sapiens nature
or the nature of Lions or Oxen, etc., or should we first set down common
attributes or a common character (PA 639a 15-19, my tr.).
In other words, the methodology of the specialist
would be to observe and catalogue each separate species by itself. The
generalist, on the other hand, is drawn to making more global connections
through an understanding of the common character of many species. Both skills
are needed. Here and elsewhere Aristotle demonstrates the limitations of a
single mode of discovery. We cannot simply set out a single path toward scientific
investigation—whether it be demonstrative (logical) exactness (the specialist’s
understanding) or holistic understanding (the generalist’s knowledge). Neither
direction (specialist or generalist) is the one and only way to truth. Really,
it is a little of both working in tandem. Sometimes one half takes the lead and
sometimes the other. The adoption of several methods is a cornerstone of
Aristotelian pluralism, a methodological principle that characterizes much of
his work.
When discussing biological science, Aristotle presents
the reader two directions: (a) the modes of discovery (genetic order) and (b)
the presentation of a completed science (logical order). In the mode of
discovery, the specialist sets out all the phenomena in as much detail as possible
while the generalist must use her inter-generic knowledge to sort out what may
or may not be significant in the event taking place before her. This is because
in the mode of discovery, the investigator is in the genetic order. Some
possible errors that could be made in this order (for example) might be
mistaking certain animal behaviors for an end for which they were not intended.
For example, it is very easy to mistake mating behavior for aggressive
territorial behavior. Since the generalist has seen many different types of
animals, she may be in the best position (on the basis of generic analogy) to
classify the sort of behavior in question.
In the mode of discovery one begins with the
phenomenon and then seeks to create a causal explanation (PA 646a 25). But how
does one go about doing this? In the Posterior
Analytics II.19, Aristotle suggests a process of induction that
begins with the particular and then moves to the universal. Arriving at the
universal entails a comprehensive understanding of some phenomenon. For
example, if one wanted to know whether fish sleep, one would first observe fish
in their environment. If one of the behaviors of the fish meets the common
understanding of sleep (such as being deadened to outside stimulus, showing little
to no movement, and so forth), then one may move to the generalization that
fish sleep (On Sleeping and Waking 455b
8, cf. On Dreams 458b 9).
But one cannot stop there. Once one has determined that fish sleep (via the
inductive mode of discovery), it is now up to the researcher to ferret out the
causes and reasons why, in a systematic fashion. This second step is the mode
of presentation. In this mode the practitioner of biological science seeks to
understand why the universal is as it is. Going back to the example of sleeping
fish, the scientist would ask why fish need to sleep. Is it by analogy to
humans and other animals that seem to gather strength through sleep? What ways
might sleep be dangerous (say by opening the individual fish to being eaten)? What
do fish do to avoid this?
These, and other questions require the practitioner to
work back and forth with what has been set down in the mode of discovery for
the purpose of providing an explanation. The most important tools for this
exercise are the two modes of causal explanation.
4. The Two Modes of Causal Explanation
For Aristotle there are four causes: material,
efficient, formal, and final. The material cause is characterized as “That out
of which something existing becomes” (Phys.
194b 24). The material has the potential for the range of final
products. Within the material is, in a potential sense, that which is to be
formed. Obviously, one piece of wood or metal has the potential to be many
artifacts; yet the possibilities are not infinite. The material itself puts
constraint upon what can be produced from it. One can execute designs in glass,
for example, which could never be brought forth from brass.
The efficient cause is depicted as “that from whence
comes the first principle of kinetic change or rest” (Phys. 194b 30). Aristotle gives the
example of a male fathering a child as showing an efficient cause. The
efficient cause is the trigger that starts a process moving.
The formal cause constitutes the essence of something
while the final cause is the purpose of something. For example, Aristotle
believed the tongue to be for the purpose of either talking or not. If the
tongue was for the purpose of talking (final cause), then it had to be shaped
in a certain way, wide and supple so that it might form subtle differences in
sound (formal cause). In this way the purpose of the tongue for speaking
dovetails with the structural way it might be brought about (P.A. 660a 27-32).
It is generally the case that Aristotle in his
biological science interrelates the final and formal causes. For example
Aristotle says that the efficient cause may be inadequate to explain change. In
the On Generation and Corruption 336a
Aristotle states that all natural efficient causes are regulated by formal
causes. “It is clear then that fire itself acts and is acted upon.” What this
means is that while the fire does act as efficient cause, the manner of this action is regulated by a
formal/final cause. The formal cause (via the doctrine of natural place—that
arranges an ascending hierarchy among the elements, earth, water, air and fire)
dictates that fire is the highest level of the sub-lunar phenomena. Thus, its
essence defines its purpose, namely, to travel upward toward its own natural
place. In this way the formal and final cause act together to guide the actions
of fire (efficient cause) to point upward toward its natural place.
Aristotle (at least in the biological works) invokes a
strategy of redundant explanation. Taken at its simplest level, he gives four
accounts of everything. However, in the actual practice, it comes about that he
really only offers two accounts. In the first account he presents a case for
understanding an event via material/kinetic means. For the sake of simplicity,
let us call this the ME (materially-based causal explanation) account.
In the second case he presents aspects of essence
(formal cause) and purpose (final cause). These are presented together. For the
sake of simplicity, let us call this the TE (teleologically-based causal
explanation) account. For an example of how these work together, consider
respiration.
Aristotle believes that material and efficient causes
can give one account of the motions of the air in and out of the lungs for
respiration. But this is only part of the story. One must also consider the
purpose of respiration and how this essence affects the entire organism (PA
642a 31-642b 4). Thus the combination of the efficient and material causes are
lumped together as one sort of explanation ME that focus upon how the nature of
hot and cold air form a sort of current that brings in new air and exhales the
old. The final and formal causes are linked together as another sort of
explanation TE that is tied to why we have respiration in the first place.
In Aristotle’s account respiration we are presented
with a partner to TE and ME: necessity. When necessity attaches itself to ME it
is called simple or absolute necessity. When necessity attaches itself to TE it
is called conditional necessity. Let us return to our example of respiration and
examine these concepts in more detail.
First, then there is the formal/final cause of
respiration. Respiration exists so that air might be brought into the body for
the creation of pneuma (a
vital force essential for life). If there were no respiration, there would be
no intake of air and no way for it to be heated in the region of the heart and
turned intopneuma—an element
necessary for life among the blooded animals who live out of water. Thus the TE
for respiration is for the sake of producing an essential raw material for the
creation of pneuma.
The second mode of explanation, ME, concerns the
material and efficient causes related to respiration. These have to do with the
manner of a quasi-gas law theory. The hot air in the lungs will tend to stay
there unless it is pushed out by the cold incoming air that hurries its exit
(cf. On Breath 481b 11).
(This is because ‘hot’ and ‘cold’ are two of the essential contraries hot/cold
& wet/dry). It is the material natures of the elements that dictate its
motions. This is the realm of the ME.
ME is an important mode of explanation because it
grounds the practitioner in the empirical facts so that he may not incline
himself to offer mere a priori causal
accounts. When one is forced to give material and kinetic accounts of some
event, then one is grounded in the tangible dynamics of what is happening. This
is one important requirement for knowledge.
Now to necessity. Necessity can be represented as a
modal operator that can attach itself to either TE or to ME. When it attaches
itself to TE, the result is conditional necessity. In conditional necessity one
must always begin with the end to be achieved. For example, if one assumes the
teleological assumption of natural efficiency, Nature does nothing in vain (GA
741b 5, cf. 739b20, et. al.) then the functions of various animal parts must be
viewed within that frame. If we know that respiration is necessary for life,
then what animal parts are necessary to allow respiration within different
species? The acceptance of the end of respiration causes the investigator to
account for how it can occur within a species. The same could be said for other
given ends such as “gaining nutrition,” “defending one’s self from attack,” and
“reproduction,” among others. When the biologist begins his investigation with
some end (whether in the mode of discovery or the mode of scientific
presentation), he is creating an account of conditional necessity.
The other sort of necessity is absolute necessity that
is the result of matter following its nature (such as fire moving to its
natural place). The very nature of the material, itself, creates the
dynamics—such as the quasi gas law interactions between the hot and cold air in
the lungs. These dynamics may be described without proximate reference to the
purpose of the event. In this way ME can function by itself along with simple
necessity to give one complete account of an event.
In biological science Aristotle believes that
conditional necessity is the most useful of the two necessities in discovery
and explanation (PA 639b 25). This is because, in biology, there is a sense
that the entire explanation always requires the purpose to set out the
boundaries of what is and what is not significant. However, in his practice it
is most often the case that Aristotle employs two complete accounts ME and TE
in order to reveal different modes of explanation according to his doctrine of
pluralism.
5. Aristotle’s Theory of Soul
The word for ‘soul’ in Aristotle is psuche. In Latin it is translated
as anima. For many
readers, it is the use of the Latin term (particularly as it was used by
Christian, Moslem, and Jewish theologians) that forms the basis of our modern
understanding of the word. Under the theological tradition, the soul meant an
immaterial, detached ruling power within a human. It was immortal and went to
God after death. This tradition gave rise to Descartes’ metaphysical dualism:
the doctrine that there are two sorts of things that exist (soul and matter),
and that soul ruled matter.
Aristotle does not think of soul as the aforementioned
theologians do. This is because matter (hyle)
and shape (morphe) combine to
create a unity not a duality. The philosopher can intellectually abstract out
the separate constituents, but in reality they are always united. This unity is
often termed hylomorphism (after its root words). Using the terminology of the
last section we can identify hyle with
ME and morphe with TE.
Thus, Aristotle’s doctrine of the soul (understood as hylomorphism) represents
a unity of form and function within matter.
From the biological perspective, soul demarcates three
sorts of living things: plants, animals, and human beings. In this way soul
acts as the cause of a body’s being alive (De An 415b 8). This amalgamation (soul and body) exhibits itself
through the presentation of a particular power that characterizes what it means
to be alive for that sort of living thing.
The soul is the form of a living body thus
constituting its first actuality. Together the body and soul form an
amalgamation. This is because when we analyze the whole into its component
parts the particular power of the amalgamation is lost. Matter without TE, as
we have seen, acts through the nature of its elements (earth, air, fire, and
water) and not for its organic purpose. An example that illustrates the
relationship between form and matter is the human eye. When an eye is situated
in a living body, the matter (and the motions of that matter) of the eye works
with the other parts of the body to present the actualization of a particular
power: sight. When governed by the actuality (or fulfillment) of its purpose,
an eyeball can see (De An 412b 17). Both the matter of the eyeball and its
various neural connections (hyle, understood
as ME) along with the formal and final causes (morphe, understood as TE) are
necessary for sight. Each part has its particular purpose, and that purpose is
given through its contribution to the basic tasks associated with essence of
the sort of thing in question: plant, animal, human.
It is important not to slip into the theological cum
Cartesian sense of anima here.
To say that plants and animals have souls is not to assert that there is a
Divine rose garden or hound Heaven. We must remember that soul for Aristotle is
a hylomorphic unity representing a monism and not a dualism. (The rational
soul’s status is less clear since it is situated in no particular organ since
Aristotle rejected the brain as the organ of thinking relegating it to a
cooling mechanism, PA652b 21-25). It is the dynamic, vital organizing principle
of life—nothing more, nothing less.
Plants exhibit the most basic power that living
organisms possess: nutrition and reproduction (De An 414a 31). The purpose of a
plant is to take in and process materials in such a way that the plant grows.
Several consequences follow (for the most part) from an individual plant having
a well-operating nutritive soul. Let’s examine one sort of plant, a tree. If a
plant exhibits excellence in taking in and processing nutrition it will exhibit
various positive effects. First, the tree will have tallness and girth that
will see it through different weather conditions. Second, it will live longer.
Third, it will drop lots of seeds giving rise to other trees. Thus, if we were
to compare two individual trees (of the same species), and one was tall and
robust while the other was small and thin, then we would be able to render a
judgment about the two individual trees on the basis of their fulfillment of
their purpose as plants within that species. The tall and robust tree of that
species would be a better tree (functionally). The small and thin tree would be
condemned as failing to fulfill its purpose as a plant within that species.
Animals contain the nutritive soul plus some of the
following powers: appetite, sensation, and locomotion (De An 414a 30, 414b
1-415a 13). Now, not all animals have all the same powers. For example, some
(like dogs) have a developed sense of smell, while others (like cats) have a
developed ability to run quickly with balance. This makes simple comparisons
between species more difficult, but within one species the same sort of
analysis used with plants also holds. That is, between two individual dogs one
dog can (for example) smell his prey up to 200 meters away while
the other dog can only detect his prey up to 50 meters. (This assumes
that being able to detect prey from a distance allows the individual to eat
more often.) The first dog is better because he has fulfilled his soul’s
function better than the second. The first dog is thus a good dog while the
second a bad example of one. What is important here is that animals judged as
animals must fulfill that power (soul) particular to it specifically in order
to be functionally excellent. This means that dogs (for example) are proximately
judged on their olfactory sense and remotely upon their ability to take in
nutrition and to reproduce.
Humans contain the nutritive soul and the
appetitive-sensory-locomotive souls along with the rational soul. This power is
given in a passive, active, and imaginative sense (De An III 3-5). What this
means is that first there is a power in the rational soul to perceive sensation
and to process it in such a way that it is intelligible. Next, one is able to
use the data received in the first step as material for analysis and
reflection. This involves the active agency of the mind. Finally, the result
(having both a sensory and ratiocinative element) can be arranged in a novel
fashion so that the universal mixes with the perceived particular. This is
imagination (De An III.3). For example, one might perceive in step-one that
your door is hanging at a slant. In step-two you examine the hinges and ponder
why the door is hanging in just this way. Finally, in step-three you consider
types of solutions that might solve the problem—such as taking a plane to the
top of the door, or inserting a “shim” behind one of the hinges. You make your
decision about this door
in front of you based upon your assessment of the various generic solutions.
The rational soul, thus understood as a multi-step
imaginative process, gives rise to theoretical and practical knowledge that, in
turn, have other sub-divisions (EN VI). Just as the single nutritive soul of
plants was greatly complicated by the addition of souls for the animals, so also
is the situation even more complicated with the addition of the rational soul
for humans. This is because it has so many different applications. For example,
one person may know right and wrong and can act on this knowledge and create
habits of the same while another may have productive knowledge of an artist who
is able to master the functional requirements of his craft in order to produce
well-wrought artifacts. Just as it is hard to compare cats and dogs among
animal souls, so it is difficult to judge various instantiations of excellence
among human rational souls. However, it is clear that between two persons
compared on their ethical virtues and two artists compared on their productive
wisdom, we may make intra-category judgments about each. These sorts of
judgments begin with a biological understanding of what it means to be a human
being and how one may fulfill her biological function based on her possession
of the human rational soul (understood in one of the sub-categories of reason).
Again, a biological understanding of the soul has implications beyond the field
of biology/psychology.
6. The Biological Practice: Outlines of a Systematics
Systematics is the study of how one ought to create a
system of biological classification and thus perform taxonomy. (“Systematics”
is not to be confused with being a “systematic philosopher.” The former term
has a technical meaning related to the theoretical foundations of animal
classification and taxonomy. The latter phrase has to do with a tightly
structured interlocking philosophical account.) In Aristotle’s logical works,
he creates a theory of definition. According to Aristotle, the best way to
create a definition is to find the proximate group in which the type of thing
resides. For example, humans are a type of thing (species) and their proximate group is animal (or blooded
animal). The proximate group is called thegenus.
Thus the genus is a larger group of which the species is merely one proper
subset. What marks off that particular species as unique? This is the differentia or the essential defining
trait. In our example with humans the differentia is “rationality.” Thus the
definition of “human” is a rational animal. “Human” is the species, “animal” is
the genus and “rationality” is the differentia.
In a similar way, Aristotle adapts his logical theory
of genus and species to biology. By thinking in terms of species and their
proximate genus, Aristotle makes a statement about the connections between
various types of animals. Aristotle does not create a full-blown classification
system that can describe all animals, but he does lay the theoretical
foundations for such.
The first overarching categories are the blooded and
the non-blooded animals. The animals covered by this distinction roughly
correspond to the modern distinction between vertebrates and invertebrates.
There are also two classes of dualizers that are animals that fit somewhat
between categories. Here is a sketch of the categorization:
I. Blooded Animals
A. Live bearing animals
1. Homo Sapiens2. Other mammals without a
distinction for primates
B. Egg-laying animals
1. Birds2. Fish
I. Non-Blooded Animals
A. Shell skinned sea animals:
testaceaB. Soft shelled sea animals: Crustacea
C. Non-shelled soft skinned sea animals:
Cephalopods
D. Insects
E. Bees
I. Dualizers (animals that share properties of
more than one group)
A. Whales, seals and porpoises—they give live
birth yet they live in the seaB. Bats—they have four appendages yet they
fly
C. Sponges—they act like both plants and like
animals
Aristotle’s proto-system of classification differs
from that of his predecessors who used habitat and other non-functional
criteria to classify animals. For example, one theory commonly set out three
large groups: air, land, and sea creatures. Because of the functional
orientation of Aristotle’s TE, Aristotle repudiates any classification system
based upon non-functional accidents. What is important is that the primary
activities of life are carried out efficiently through specially designated
body parts.
Though Aristotle’s work on classification is by no
means comprehensive (but is rather a series of reflections on how to create
one), it is appropriate to describe it as meta-systematics. Such reflections
are consistent with his other key explanatory concepts of functionalism (TE and
ME) as well as his work on logic in the Organon
with respect to the utilization of genus and species. Though
incomplete, this again is a blueprint of how to construct a systematics. The
general structure of meta-systematics also acts as an independent principle
that permits Aristotle to examine animals together that are functionally
similar. Such a move enhances the reliability of analogy as a tool of
explanation.
7. “The more and the less” and “Epi to polu”
“The more and the less” is an explanatory concept that
is allied to the ME account. Principally, it is a way that individuation occurs
in the non-uniform parts. Aristotle distinguishes two sorts of parts in
animals: the uniform and the non-uniform. The uniform parts are those that if you
dumped them into a bucket and cut the bucket in half, they would still remain
the same. For example, blood is a uniform part. Dump blood into a bucket and
cut it in half and it’s still the same blood (just half the quantity). The same
is true of tissue, cartilage, tendons, skin, et al. Non-uniform parts change
when the bucket test is applied. If you dump a lung into a bucket and cut it in
half, you no longer have a proper organ. The same holds true of other organs:
heart, liver, pancreas, and so forth, as well as the skeleton (Uniform Parts—PA
646b 20, 648b, 650a 20, 650b, 651b 20, 652a 23; Non-Uniform Parts—PA 656b 25,
622a 17, 665b 20, 683a 20, 684a 25.)
When an individual has excess nutrition (trophe), the excess (perittoma) often is distributed all around
(GA 734b 25). An external observer does not perceive the changes to the uniform
parts—except, perhaps, stomach fat. But such an observer would perceive the
difference in a child who has been well fed (whose non-uniform parts are
bigger) than one who hasn’t. The difference is accounted for by the principle
of the more and the less.
How does an external observer differentiate between
any two people? The answer is that the non-uniform parts (particularly the
skeletal structure) differ. Thus, one person’s nose is longer, another stands
taller, a third is broader in the shoulders, etc. We all have noses, stand
within a range of height and broadness of shoulders, etc. The particular mix
that we each possess makes us individuals.
Sometimes, this mix goes beyond the range of the
species (eidos). In these
instances a part becomes non-functional because it has too much material or too
little. Such situations are beyond the natural range one might expect within
the species. Because of this, the instance involved is characterized as being
unnatural (para phusin).
The possibility of unnatural events occurring in
nature affects the status of explanatory principles in biology. We remember
from above that there are two sorts of necessity: conditional and absolute. The
absolute necessity never fails. It is the sort of necessity that one can apply
to the stars that exist in the super lunar realm. One can create star charts of
the heavens that will be accurate for a thousand years forward or backward.
This is because of the mode of absolute necessity.
However, because conditional necessity depends upon
its telos, and because of the principle of the more and the less that is
non-teleologically (ME) driven, there can arise a sort of spontaneity
(cf. automaton, Phys. II.6)
that can alter the normal, expected execution of a task because spontaneity is
purposeless. In these cases the input from the material cause is greater or
lesser than is usually the case. The result is an unnatural outcome based upon
the principle of the more and the less. An example of this might be obesity.
Nourishment is delivered to the body in a hierarchical fashion beginning with
the primary needs. When all biological needs are met, then the excess goes into
hair, nails and body fat. Excess body fat can impair proper function, but not
out of design.
Because of the possibility of spontaneity and its
unintended consequences, the necessary operative in biological events
(conditional necessity) is only “for the most part” (hôs epi
to polu). We cannot expect biological explanatory principles to be
of the same order as those of the stars. Ceteris paribis principles are the best the biological realm
can give. This brute fact gives rise to a different set of epistemic
expectations than are often raised in the Prior Analytics and the Posterior Analytics. Our expectations for biology are for
general rules that are true in most cases but have many exceptions. This means
that biology cannot be an exact science, unlike astronomy. If there are always
going to be exceptions that are contrary to nature, then the biologist must do
his biology with toleration for these sorts of peripheral anomalies. This
disposition is characterized by the doctrine of epi to polu.
8. Significant Achievements and Mistakes
This section will highlight a few of Aristotle’s
biological achievements from the perspective of over 2,300 years of hindsight.
For simplicity’s sake let us break these up into “bad calls” (observations and
conclusions that have proven to be wrong) and “good calls” (observations and
conclusions that have proven to be very accurate).
We begin with the bad calls: let’s start with a few of
Aristotle’s mistakes. First, Aristotle believed that thinking occurred in the
region around the heart and not in the brain (a cooling organ, PA 652b 21-25,
cf. HA 514a 16-22). Second, Aristotle thought that men were hotter than women
(the opposite is the case). Third, Aristotle overweighed the male contribution
in reproduction. Fourth, little details are often amiss such as the number of
teeth in women. Fifth, Aristotle believed that spontaneous generation could
occur. For example, Aristotle observed that from animal dung certain flies
could appear (even though careful observation did not reveal any flies mating
and laying their eggs in the dung. The possibility of the eggs already existing
in the abdomen of the animal did not occur to Aristotle.) However, these sorts
of mistakes are more often than not the result of an a priori principle such as “women being
colder and less perfectly formed than men” or the application of his method on
(in principle) unobservables—such as human conception in which it is posited
that the male provides the efficient, formal, and final cause while the woman
provides merely the material cause.
Good Calls: Aristotle examined over 500 different
species of animals. Some species came from fishermen, hunters, farmers, and
perhaps Alexander. Many other species were viewed in nature by Aristotle. There
are some very exact observations made by Aristotle during his stay at Lesbos.
It is virtually certain that his early dissection skills were utilized solely
upon animals (due to the social prohibition on dissecting humans). One example
of this comes from the Generation of
Animals in which Aristotle breaks open fertilized chicken eggs at
carefully controlled intervals to observe when visible organs were generated.
The first organ Aristotle saw was the heart. (In fact it is the spinal cord and
the beginnings of the nervous system, but this is not visible without employing
modern staining techniques.) On eggs opened later, Aristotle saw other organs.
This led Aristotle to come out against a popular theory of conception and
development entitled, “the pre-formation theory.” In the pre-formation theory,
whose advocates extended until the eighteenth century, all the parts appear all
at once and development is merely the growth of these essential parts. The
contrary theory that Aristotle espouses is the epigenetic theory. According to
epigenesis, the parts are created in a nested hierarchical order. Thus, through
his observation, Aristotle saw that the heart was formed first, then he
postulated that other parts were formed (also backed-up by observation).
Aristotle concludes,
I mean, for instance, not that the heart once formed,
fashions the liver, and then the liver fashions something else; but that the
one is formed after the other (just as man is formed in time after a child),
not by it. The reason of this is that so far as the things formed by nature or
by human art are concerned, the formation of that which is potentially brought about by that which
is in actuality; so that
the form of B would have to be contained in A, e.g., the form of liver would
have to be in the heart—which is absurd. (GA 734a 28-35, Peck trans.)
In epigenesis the controlling process of development
operates according to the TE plan of creating the most important parts first.
Since the heart is the principle (arche)
of the body, being the center of blood production and sensation/intelligence,
it is appropriate that it should be created first. Then other parts such as the
liver, etc. are then created in their appropriate order. The
epigenesis-preformation debate lasted two thousand years and Aristotle got it
right.
Another interesting observation by Aristotle is the
discovery of the reproductive mode of the dog shark,Mustelus laevis (HA 6.10, 565b 1ff.). This species is
externally viviparous (live bearing) yet internally oviparous (egg bearing).
Such an observation could only have come from dissections and careful
observations.
Another observation concerns the reproductive habits
of cuttlefish. In this process of hectocotylization, the sperm of the Argonauta among other allied species
comes in large spermataphores that the male transfers to the mantle cavity of
the female. This complicated maneuver, described in HA 524a 4-5, 541b 9-15, cf.
544a 12, GA 720b 33, was not fully verified by moderns until 1959!
Though Aristotle’s observations on bees in HA seems to
be entirely from the beekeeper’s point of view (HA 625b7-22), he does note that
there are three classes of bees and that sexual reproduction requires that one
class give way. He begins his discussion in the Generation of Animals with the following
remark, “The generation of bees is beset with many problems” (GA 759a 9). If
there are three classes and two genders, then something is amiss. Aristotle
goes through what he feels to be all the possibilities. Though the observations
are probably second-hand, Aristotle is still able to evaluate the data. He
employs his systematic theory using the over-riding meta-principle that Nature
always acts in an orderly way (GA 760a 32) to form his explanation of the
function of each type of bee. This means that there must be a purposeful
process (TE) that guides generation. However, since neither Aristotle nor the
beekeepers had ever seen bee copulation, and since Aristotle allows for asexual
generation in some fish, he believes that the case of bees offers him another
case in which one class is sterile (complies with modern theory on worker bees),
another class creates its own kind and another (this is meant to correspond to
the Queen bee—that Aristotle calls a King Bee because it has a stinger and
females in nature never have defensive weapons), while the third class creates
not its own class but another (this is the drone).
Aristotle has got some of this right and some of it
wrong. What he has right is first, bees are unusual in having three classes.
Second, one class is infertile and works for the good of the whole. Third, one
class (the Queen) is a super-reproducer. However, in the case of bees it is
Aristotle’s method rather than his results that stirs admiration. Three meta-principles cause particular note:
- Reproduction works with two groups not three. The quickest “solution” would have been to make one group sterile and then make the other two male and female. [This would have been the correct response.] However, since none of the beekeepers reported anything like reproductive behavior among bees and because Aristotle’s own limited observations also do not note this, he is reluctant to make such a reply. It is on the basis of the phainomena that Aristotle rejects bee copulation (GA 759a 10).
- Aristotle holds that a priori argument alone is not enough. One must square the most likely explanation with the observed facts.
- Via analogy, Aristotle notes that some fish seem not to reproduce and even some flies are generated spontaneously. Thus, assigning the roles to the various classes that he does, Aristotle does not create a sui generis instance. By analogy to other suppositions of his biological theory, Aristotle is able to “solve” a troublesome case via reference to analogy. (Aristotle is also admirably cautious about his own theory, saying that more work is needed.)
What is most important in Aristotle’s accomplishments
is his combination of keen observations with a critical scientific method that
employs his systematic categories to solve problems in biology and then link
these to other issues in human life.
9. Conclusion
Since Aristotle’s biological works comprise almost a
third of his writings that have come down to us, and since these writings may
have occurred early in his career, it is very possible that the influence of
the biological works upon Aristotle’s other writings is considerable. Aristotle’s
biological works (so often neglected) should be brought to the fore, not only
in the history of biology, but also as a way of understanding some of
Aristotle’s non-biological writings.
10. References and Further Reading
a. Primary Text
- Bekker, Immanuel (ed) update by Olof Gigon , Aristotelis Opera. Berlin, Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1831-1870, rpt. W. de Gruyter, 1960-1987.
b. Key Texts in Translation
- Barnes, Jonathan (ed). The Complete Works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.
- The Clarendon Series of Aristotle:
- Balme, David (tr and ed). Updated by Allan Gotthelf, De Partibus Animalium I with De Generatione Animalium I (with passages from II 1-3). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).
- Lennox, James G. (tr and ed) Aristotle on the Parts of Animals I-4. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
- The Loeb Series of Aristotle (opposite pages of Greek and English).
c. Selected Secondary Sources
- Balme, David. “Aristotle’s Use of Differentiae in Zoology.” Aristote et les Problèms de Méthode.Louvain: Publications Universitaires 1961.
- Balme, David. “GENOS and EIDOS in Aristotle’s Biology” The Classical Quarterly. 12 (1962): 81-88.
- Balme, David. “Aristotle’s Biology was not Essentialist” Archiv Für Geschichte der Philosophie. 62.1 (1980): 1-12.
- Bourgey, Louis. Observation et Experiénce chez Aristote. Paris: J. Vrin, 1955.
- Boylan, Michael. "Mechanism and Teleology in Aristotle's Biology" Apeiron 15.2 (1981): 96-102.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Digestive and 'Circulatory' Systems in Aristotle's Biology" Journal of the History of Biology 15.1 (1982): 89-118.
- Boylan, Michael. Method and Practice in Aristotle’s Biology. Lanham, MD and London: University Press of America, 1983.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Hippocratic and Galenic Challenges to Aristotle's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 15.1 (1984): 83-112.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Place of Nature in Aristotle's Biology" Apeiron 19.1 (1985).
- Boylan, Michael. "Galen's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 19.1 (1986): 44-77.
- Boylan, Michael. "Monadic and SystemicTEleology" in Modern Problems in Teleology ed. Nicholas Rescher (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1986).
- Charles, David. Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
- Deverreux, Daniel and Pierre Pellegrin. Eds. Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote. Paris: Éditions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique,1990.
- Düring, Ingemar. Aristotles De Partibus Animalium, Critical and Literary Commentary. Goeteborg, 1943, rpt. NY.: Garland, 1980.
- Ferejohn, M. The Origins of Aristotelian Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990.
- Gotthelf, Allan and James G. Lennox, eds. Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. NY: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
- Grene, Marjorie. A Portrait of Aristotle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963.
- Joly, Robert. “La Charactérologie Antique Jusqu’ à Aristote. Revue Belge de Philologie et d’Histoire40 (1962): 5-28.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. Wissenscaft und Methode: Interpretationen zur Aristotelischen Theorie der Naturwissenschaft. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. Aristoteles und die moderne Wissenschaft Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1998.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. “Aristotles’ wissenschaftliche Methode in seinen zoologischen Schriften” in Wörhle, G., ed. Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften. Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1999, pp. 103-123.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. “Zoologische Sammelwerk in der Antike” in Wörhle, G., ed. Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften. Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner 1999, pp. 181-198.
- Kung, Joan. “Some Aspects of Form in Aristotle’s Biology” Nature and System 2 (1980): 67-90.
- Kung, Joan. “Aristotle on Thises, Suches and the Third Man Argument” Phronesis 26 (1981): 207-247.
- Le Blonde, Jean Marie. Aristote, Philosophie de la Vie. Paris: Éditions Montaigne, 1945.
- Lesher, James. “NOUS in the Parts of Animals.” Phronesis 18 (1973): 44-68.
- Lennox, James. “Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation” Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (1982): 219-232.
- Lennox, James. “The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology” Philosophical Topics 25.1 (1999): 1-16.
- Lennox, James. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Sciences. NY: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. “Right and Left in Greek Philosophy” Journal of Hellenic Studies. 82 (1962): 67-90.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Polarity and Analogy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. “Saving the Appearances” Classical Quarterly. n.s. 28 (1978): 202-222.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Magic, Reason, and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. The Revolutions of Wisdom. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1987
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Aristotelian Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
- Louis, Pierre. “La Génération Spontanée chez Aristote” Congrèss International d’Histoire des Sciences (1968): 291-305.
- Louis, Pierre. La Découverte de la Vie. Paris: Hermann, 1975.
- Owen, G.E.L. “TITHENAI TA PHAINOMENA” Aristote et les Problèms de Méthode. Louvain, 1975.
- Owen, G.E.L. The Platonism of Aristotle. London: British Academy: Dawes Hicks Lecture on Philosophy, 1965.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. La Classification des Animaux chez Aristote: Statut de la Biologie et Unite de l’Aristotélisme. Paris: Societé d’édition “Les Belles Lettres,” 1982.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. “Logical Difference and Biological Difference: The Unity of Aristotle’s Thought” in Gotthelf, Allan and James G. Lennox, eds. Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. NY: Cambridge University Press, 1987, pp. 313-338.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. “Taxonomie, moriologie, division” in Deverreux, Daniel and Pierre Pellegrin. Eds.Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote. Paris, 1990, 37-48.
- Preus, Anthony. “Aristotle’s Parts of Animals 2.16 659b 13-19: Is it Authentic?” Classical Quarterly18.2 (1968): 170-178.
- Preus, Anthony. “Nature Uses. . . .” Apeiron 3.2 (1969): 20-33.
- Preus, Anthony. Science and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Biological Works. NY: Olhms, 1975.
- Preus, Anthony. “Eidos as Norm” Nature and System 1 (1979): 79-103.
- Solmsen, Friedrich. Aristotle’s System of the Physical World: A Comparison with his Predecessors.Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1960.
- Sorabji, Richard. Necessity, Cause, and Blame. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1980.
- Thompson, D’Arcy. Aristotle as Biologist. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1913.
- Thompson, D’Arcy. Growth and Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1917.
- Ulmer, K. Wahrheit, Kunst und Natur bei Aristotles. Tübingen: M. Niemayer, 1953.
- Witt, Charlotte. Substance and Essence in Aristotle: An Interpretation of Metaphysics VII-IX.Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989.
- Wörhle, Georg and Jochen Althoff, eds. Biologie in Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften (series). Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1999.
Author Information
Aristotle: Biology
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.) may be
said to be the first biologist in the Western tradition. Though there are
physicians and other natural philosophers who remark on various flora and fauna
before Aristotle, none of them brings to his study a systematic critical
empiricism. Aristotle’s biological science is important to understand, not only
because it gives us a view into the history and philosophy of science, but also
because it allows us more deeply to understand his non-biological works, since
certain key concepts from Aristotle’s biology repeat themselves in his other
writings. Since a significant portion of the corpus of Aristotle’s work is on
biology, it is natural to expect his work in biology to resonate in his other
writings. One may, for example, use concepts from the biological works to
better understand the ethics or metaphysics of Aristotle.
This article will begin with a brief explanation of
his biological views and move toward several key explanatory concepts that
Aristotle employs. These concepts are essential because they stand as
candidates for a philosophy of biology. If Aristotle’s principles are
insightful, then he has gone a long way towards creating the first systematic
and critical system of biological thought. It is for this reason (rather than
the particular observations themselves) that moderns are interested in
Aristotle’s biological writings.
Table of Contents
- His Life
- The Scope of Aristotle’s Biological Works
- The Specialist and the Generalist
- The Two Modes of Causal Explanation
- Aristotle’s Theory of Soul
- The Biological Practice: Outlines of a Systematics
- “The more and the less” and “Epi to polu”
- Significant Achievements and Mistakes
- Conclusion
- References and Further Reading
1. His Life
Aristotle was born in the year 384 B.C. in the town of
Stagira (the modern town Stavros), a coastal Macedonian town to the north of
Greece. He was raised at the court of Amyntas where he probably met and was
friends with Philip (later to become king and father to Alexander, the Great).
When Aristotle was around 18, he was sent to Athens to study in Plato’s
Academy. Aristotle spent twenty years at the Academy until Plato’s death,
although Diogenes says Aristotle left before Plato’s death. When Plato was
succeeded by his nephew, Speusippus, as head of the Academy, Aristotle accepted
an invitation to join a former student, Hermeias, who was gathering a Platonic
circle about him in Assos in Mysia (near Troy). Aristotle spent three years in
this environment. During this time, he may have done some of the natural
investigations that later became The
History of Animals.
At the end of Aristotle’s stay in Mysia, he moved to
Lesbos (an adjacent island). This move may have been prompted by Theophrastus,
a fellow of the Academy who was much influenced by Aristotle. It is probable
(according to D’Arcy Thompson) that Aristotle performed some important
biological investigations during this period.
Aristotle returned to Athens (circa 334-5). This began
a period of great productivity. He rented some grounds in woods sacred to
Apollo. It was here that Aristotle set-up his school (Diog. Laert V, 51).
At his school Aristotle also accumulated a large
number of manuscripts and created a library that was a model for later
libraries in Alexandria and Pergamon. According to one tradition, Alexander
(his former pupil) paid him a handsome sum of money each year as a form of
gratitude (as well as some exotic animals for Aristotle to study that Alexander
encountered in his conquests).
At the death of Alexander in 323, Athens once again
was full of anti-Macedonian sentiment. A charge of impiety was brought against
Aristotle due to a poem he had written for Hermeias. One martyr for philosophy
(Socrates) was enough for Aristotle and so he left his school to his colleague,
Theophrastus, and fled to the Macedonian Chalcis. Here in 322 he died of a
disease that is still the subject of speculation.
2. The Scope of Aristotle’s Biological Works
There is some dispute as to which works should be
classified as the biological works of Aristotle. This is indeed a contentious
question that is especially difficult for a systematic philosopher such as
Aristotle. Generally speaking, a systematic philosopher is one who constructs
various philosophical distinctions that, in turn, can be applied to a number of
different contexts. Thus, a distinction such as “the more and the less” that
has its roots in biology explaining that certain animal parts are greater
(bigger) among some individuals and smaller among others, can also be used in
the ethics as a cornerstone of the doctrine of the mean as a criterion for
virtue. That is, one varies from the mean by the principle of the more and the
less. For example, if courage is the mean, then the defect of excess would be
“foolhardiness” while the defect of paucity would be “cowardice.” The boundary
between what we’d consider “biology” proper vs. what we’d think of as
psychology, philosophy of mind, and metaphysics is often hard to draw in
Aristotle. That’s because Aristotle’s understanding of biology informs his
metaphysics and philosophy of mind, but likewise, he often uses the
distinctions drawn in his metaphysics in order to deal with biological issues.
In this article, the biological works are: (a) works
that deal specifically with biological topics such as: The Parts of Animals (PA), The Generation of Animals
(GA), The History of Animals (HA), The Movement of Animals, The Progression of
Animals, On Sense and Sensible Objects, On Memory and Recollection, On Sleep
and Waking, On Dreams, On Prophecy in Sleep, On Length and Shortness of Life,
On Youth and Old Age, On Life and Death, On Respiration, On Breath, and On Plants, and (b) the work that deals with psuche (soul), On the Soul—though this work deals with
metaphysical issues very explicitly, as well. This list does not include works
such as the Metaphysics, Physics,
Posterior Analytics, Categories, Nicomachean Ethics, or The Politics even though they contain
many arguments that are augmented by an understanding of Aristotle’s biological
science. Nor does this article examine any of the reputedly lost works (listed
by ancient authors but not existing today) such as Dissections, On Composite Animals, On Sterility, On
Physiognomy, and On
Medicine . Some of these titles may have sections that have
survived in part within the present corpus, but this is doubtful.
3. The Specialist and the Generalist
The distinction between the specialist and the
generalist is a good starting point for understanding Aristotle’s philosophy of
biology. The specialist is one who has a considerable body of experience in
practical fieldwork while the generalist is one who knows many different areas
of study. This distinction is brought out in Book One of the Parts of Animals (PA). At PA 639a 1-7
Aristotle says,
In all study and investigation, be it exalted or
mundane, there appear to be two types of proficiency: one is that of exact,
scientific knowledge while the other is a generalist’s understanding. (my tr.)
Aristotle does not mean to denigrate or to exalt
either. Both are necessary for natural investigations. The generalist’s
understanding is holistic and puts some area of study into a proper genus,
while scientific knowledge deals with causes and definitions at the level of
the species. These two skills are demonstrated by the following example:
An example of what I mean is the question of whether
one should take a single species and state its differentia independently, for
example, homo sapiens nature
or the nature of Lions or Oxen, etc., or should we first set down common
attributes or a common character (PA 639a 15-19, my tr.).
In other words, the methodology of the specialist
would be to observe and catalogue each separate species by itself. The
generalist, on the other hand, is drawn to making more global connections
through an understanding of the common character of many species. Both skills
are needed. Here and elsewhere Aristotle demonstrates the limitations of a
single mode of discovery. We cannot simply set out a single path toward
scientific investigation—whether it be demonstrative (logical) exactness (the
specialist’s understanding) or holistic understanding (the generalist’s
knowledge). Neither direction (specialist or generalist) is the one and only
way to truth. Really, it is a little of both working in tandem. Sometimes one
half takes the lead and sometimes the other. The adoption of several methods is
a cornerstone of Aristotelian pluralism, a methodological principle that
characterizes much of his work.
When discussing biological science, Aristotle presents
the reader two directions: (a) the modes of discovery (genetic order) and (b)
the presentation of a completed science (logical order). In the mode of
discovery, the specialist sets out all the phenomena in as much detail as
possible while the generalist must use her inter-generic knowledge to sort out
what may or may not be significant in the event taking place before her. This
is because in the mode of discovery, the investigator is in the genetic order.
Some possible errors that could be made in this order (for example) might be
mistaking certain animal behaviors for an end for which they were not intended.
For example, it is very easy to mistake mating behavior for aggressive
territorial behavior. Since the generalist has seen many different types of
animals, she may be in the best position (on the basis of generic analogy) to
classify the sort of behavior in question.
In the mode of discovery one begins with the
phenomenon and then seeks to create a causal explanation (PA 646a 25). But how
does one go about doing this? In the Posterior
Analytics II.19, Aristotle suggests a process of induction that
begins with the particular and then moves to the universal. Arriving at the
universal entails a comprehensive understanding of some phenomenon. For
example, if one wanted to know whether fish sleep, one would first observe fish
in their environment. If one of the behaviors of the fish meets the common
understanding of sleep (such as being deadened to outside stimulus, showing
little to no movement, and so forth), then one may move to the generalization
that fish sleep (On Sleeping and Waking 455b
8, cf. On Dreams 458b 9).
But one cannot stop there. Once one has determined that fish sleep (via the
inductive mode of discovery), it is now up to the researcher to ferret out the
causes and reasons why, in a systematic fashion. This second step is the mode
of presentation. In this mode the practitioner of biological science seeks to
understand why the universal is as it is. Going back to the example of sleeping
fish, the scientist would ask why fish need to sleep. Is it by analogy to
humans and other animals that seem to gather strength through sleep? What ways
might sleep be dangerous (say by opening the individual fish to being eaten)?
What do fish do to avoid this?
These, and other questions require the practitioner to
work back and forth with what has been set down in the mode of discovery for
the purpose of providing an explanation. The most important tools for this
exercise are the two modes of causal explanation.
4. The Two Modes of Causal Explanation
For Aristotle there are four causes: material,
efficient, formal, and final. The material cause is characterized as “That out
of which something existing becomes” (Phys.
194b 24). The material has the potential for the range of final
products. Within the material is, in a potential sense, that which is to be
formed. Obviously, one piece of wood or metal has the potential to be many
artifacts; yet the possibilities are not infinite. The material itself puts
constraint upon what can be produced from it. One can execute designs in glass,
for example, which could never be brought forth from brass.
The efficient cause is depicted as “that from whence
comes the first principle of kinetic change or rest” (Phys. 194b 30). Aristotle gives the
example of a male fathering a child as showing an efficient cause. The
efficient cause is the trigger that starts a process moving.
The formal cause constitutes the essence of something
while the final cause is the purpose of something. For example, Aristotle
believed the tongue to be for the purpose of either talking or not. If the
tongue was for the purpose of talking (final cause), then it had to be shaped
in a certain way, wide and supple so that it might form subtle differences in
sound (formal cause). In this way the purpose of the tongue for speaking
dovetails with the structural way it might be brought about (P.A. 660a 27-32).
It is generally the case that Aristotle in his
biological science interrelates the final and formal causes. For example
Aristotle says that the efficient cause may be inadequate to explain change. In
the On Generation and Corruption 336a
Aristotle states that all natural efficient causes are regulated by formal
causes. “It is clear then that fire itself acts and is acted upon.” What this
means is that while the fire does act as efficient cause, the manner of this action is regulated by a
formal/final cause. The formal cause (via the doctrine of natural place—that
arranges an ascending hierarchy among the elements, earth, water, air and fire)
dictates that fire is the highest level of the sub-lunar phenomena. Thus, its
essence defines its purpose, namely, to travel upward toward its own natural
place. In this way the formal and final cause act together to guide the actions
of fire (efficient cause) to point upward toward its natural place.
Aristotle (at least in the biological works) invokes a
strategy of redundant explanation. Taken at its simplest level, he gives four
accounts of everything. However, in the actual practice, it comes about that he
really only offers two accounts. In the first account he presents a case for
understanding an event via material/kinetic means. For the sake of simplicity,
let us call this the ME (materially-based causal explanation) account.
In the second case he presents aspects of essence (formal
cause) and purpose (final cause). These are presented together. For the sake of
simplicity, let us call this the TE (teleologically-based causal explanation)
account. For an example of how these work together, consider respiration.
Aristotle believes that material and efficient causes
can give one account of the motions of the air in and out of the lungs for
respiration. But this is only part of the story. One must also consider the
purpose of respiration and how this essence affects the entire organism (PA
642a 31-642b 4). Thus the combination of the efficient and material causes are
lumped together as one sort of explanation ME that focus upon how the nature of
hot and cold air form a sort of current that brings in new air and exhales the
old. The final and formal causes are linked together as another sort of
explanation TE that is tied to why we have respiration in the first place.
In Aristotle’s account respiration we are presented
with a partner to TE and ME: necessity. When necessity attaches itself to ME it
is called simple or absolute necessity. When necessity attaches itself to TE it
is called conditional necessity. Let us return to our example of respiration
and examine these concepts in more detail.
First, then there is the formal/final cause of
respiration. Respiration exists so that air might be brought into the body for
the creation of pneuma (a
vital force essential for life). If there were no respiration, there would be
no intake of air and no way for it to be heated in the region of the heart and
turned intopneuma—an element
necessary for life among the blooded animals who live out of water. Thus the TE
for respiration is for the sake of producing an essential raw material for the
creation of pneuma.
The second mode of explanation, ME, concerns the
material and efficient causes related to respiration. These have to do with the
manner of a quasi-gas law theory. The hot air in the lungs will tend to stay
there unless it is pushed out by the cold incoming air that hurries its exit
(cf. On Breath 481b 11).
(This is because ‘hot’ and ‘cold’ are two of the essential contraries hot/cold
& wet/dry). It is the material natures of the elements that dictate its
motions. This is the realm of the ME.
ME is an important mode of explanation because it
grounds the practitioner in the empirical facts so that he may not incline
himself to offer mere a priori causal
accounts. When one is forced to give material and kinetic accounts of some
event, then one is grounded in the tangible dynamics of what is happening. This
is one important requirement for knowledge.
Now to necessity. Necessity can be represented as a
modal operator that can attach itself to either TE or to ME. When it attaches
itself to TE, the result is conditional necessity. In conditional necessity one
must always begin with the end to be achieved. For example, if one assumes the
teleological assumption of natural efficiency, Nature does nothing in vain (GA
741b 5, cf. 739b20, et. al.) then the functions of various animal parts must be
viewed within that frame. If we know that respiration is necessary for life,
then what animal parts are necessary to allow respiration within different
species? The acceptance of the end of respiration causes the investigator to
account for how it can occur within a species. The same could be said for other
given ends such as “gaining nutrition,” “defending one’s self from attack,” and
“reproduction,” among others. When the biologist begins his investigation with
some end (whether in the mode of discovery or the mode of scientific
presentation), he is creating an account of conditional necessity.
The other sort of necessity is absolute necessity that
is the result of matter following its nature (such as fire moving to its
natural place). The very nature of the material, itself, creates the
dynamics—such as the quasi gas law interactions between the hot and cold air in
the lungs. These dynamics may be described without proximate reference to the
purpose of the event. In this way ME can function by itself along with simple necessity
to give one complete account of an event.
In biological science Aristotle believes that
conditional necessity is the most useful of the two necessities in discovery
and explanation (PA 639b 25). This is because, in biology, there is a sense
that the entire explanation always requires the purpose to set out the
boundaries of what is and what is not significant. However, in his practice it
is most often the case that Aristotle employs two complete accounts ME and TE
in order to reveal different modes of explanation according to his doctrine of
pluralism.
5. Aristotle’s Theory of Soul
The word for ‘soul’ in Aristotle is psuche. In Latin it is translated
as anima. For many
readers, it is the use of the Latin term (particularly as it was used by
Christian, Moslem, and Jewish theologians) that forms the basis of our modern
understanding of the word. Under the theological tradition, the soul meant an
immaterial, detached ruling power within a human. It was immortal and went to
God after death. This tradition gave rise to Descartes’ metaphysical dualism:
the doctrine that there are two sorts of things that exist (soul and matter),
and that soul ruled matter.
Aristotle does not think of soul as the aforementioned
theologians do. This is because matter (hyle)
and shape (morphe) combine to
create a unity not a duality. The philosopher can intellectually abstract out
the separate constituents, but in reality they are always united. This unity is
often termed hylomorphism (after its root words). Using the terminology of the
last section we can identify hyle with
ME and morphe with TE.
Thus, Aristotle’s doctrine of the soul (understood as hylomorphism) represents
a unity of form and function within matter.
From the biological perspective, soul demarcates three
sorts of living things: plants, animals, and human beings. In this way soul
acts as the cause of a body’s being alive (De An 415b 8). This amalgamation (soul and body) exhibits itself
through the presentation of a particular power that characterizes what it means
to be alive for that sort of living thing.
The soul is the form of a living body thus
constituting its first actuality. Together the body and soul form an
amalgamation. This is because when we analyze the whole into its component
parts the particular power of the amalgamation is lost. Matter without TE, as
we have seen, acts through the nature of its elements (earth, air, fire, and
water) and not for its organic purpose. An example that illustrates the
relationship between form and matter is the human eye. When an eye is situated
in a living body, the matter (and the motions of that matter) of the eye works
with the other parts of the body to present the actualization of a particular
power: sight. When governed by the actuality (or fulfillment) of its purpose,
an eyeball can see (De An 412b 17). Both the matter of the eyeball and its
various neural connections (hyle, understood
as ME) along with the formal and final causes (morphe, understood as TE) are
necessary for sight. Each part has its particular purpose, and that purpose is
given through its contribution to the basic tasks associated with essence of
the sort of thing in question: plant, animal, human.
It is important not to slip into the theological cum
Cartesian sense of anima here.
To say that plants and animals have souls is not to assert that there is a
Divine rose garden or hound Heaven. We must remember that soul for Aristotle is
a hylomorphic unity representing a monism and not a dualism. (The rational
soul’s status is less clear since it is situated in no particular organ since
Aristotle rejected the brain as the organ of thinking relegating it to a
cooling mechanism, PA652b 21-25). It is the dynamic, vital organizing principle
of life—nothing more, nothing less.
Plants exhibit the most basic power that living
organisms possess: nutrition and reproduction (De An 414a 31). The purpose of a
plant is to take in and process materials in such a way that the plant grows.
Several consequences follow (for the most part) from an individual plant having
a well-operating nutritive soul. Let’s examine one sort of plant, a tree. If a
plant exhibits excellence in taking in and processing nutrition it will exhibit
various positive effects. First, the tree will have tallness and girth that
will see it through different weather conditions. Second, it will live longer.
Third, it will drop lots of seeds giving rise to other trees. Thus, if we were
to compare two individual trees (of the same species), and one was tall and
robust while the other was small and thin, then we would be able to render a
judgment about the two individual trees on the basis of their fulfillment of
their purpose as plants within that species. The tall and robust tree of that
species would be a better tree (functionally). The small and thin tree would be
condemned as failing to fulfill its purpose as a plant within that species.
Animals contain the nutritive soul plus some of the
following powers: appetite, sensation, and locomotion (De An 414a 30, 414b
1-415a 13). Now, not all animals have all the same powers. For example, some
(like dogs) have a developed sense of smell, while others (like cats) have a
developed ability to run quickly with balance. This makes simple comparisons
between species more difficult, but within one species the same sort of
analysis used with plants also holds. That is, between two individual dogs one
dog can (for example) smell his prey up to 200 meters away while the other dog
can only detect his prey up to 50 meters. (This assumes that being able to
detect prey from a distance allows the individual to eat more often.) The first
dog is better because he has fulfilled his soul’s function better than the
second. The first dog is thus a good dog while the second a bad example of one.
What is important here is that animals judged as animals must fulfill that
power (soul) particular to it specifically in order to be functionally
excellent. This means that dogs (for example) are proximately judged on their
olfactory sense and remotely upon their ability to take in nutrition and to
reproduce.
Humans contain the nutritive soul and the
appetitive-sensory-locomotive souls along with the rational soul. This power is
given in a passive, active, and imaginative sense (De An III 3-5). What this
means is that first there is a power in the rational soul to perceive sensation
and to process it in such a way that it is intelligible. Next, one is able to
use the data received in the first step as material for analysis and
reflection. This involves the active agency of the mind. Finally, the result
(having both a sensory and ratiocinative element) can be arranged in a novel
fashion so that the universal mixes with the perceived particular. This is
imagination (De An III.3). For example, one might perceive in step-one that
your door is hanging at a slant. In step-two you examine the hinges and ponder
why the door is hanging in just this way. Finally, in step-three you consider
types of solutions that might solve the problem—such as taking a plane to the
top of the door, or inserting a “shim” behind one of the hinges. You make your
decision about this door
in front of you based upon your assessment of the various generic solutions.
The rational soul, thus understood as a multi-step
imaginative process, gives rise to theoretical and practical knowledge that, in
turn, have other sub-divisions (EN VI). Just as the single nutritive soul of
plants was greatly complicated by the addition of souls for the animals, so
also is the situation even more complicated with the addition of the rational
soul for humans. This is because it has so many different applications. For
example, one person may know right and wrong and can act on this knowledge and
create habits of the same while another may have productive knowledge of an
artist who is able to master the functional requirements of his craft in order
to produce well-wrought artifacts. Just as it is hard to compare cats and dogs
among animal souls, so it is difficult to judge various instantiations of
excellence among human rational souls. However, it is clear that between two
persons compared on their ethical virtues and two artists compared on their
productive wisdom, we may make intra-category judgments about each. These sorts
of judgments begin with a biological understanding of what it means to be a
human being and how one may fulfill her biological function based on her
possession of the human rational soul (understood in one of the sub-categories
of reason). Again, a biological understanding of the soul has implications
beyond the field of biology/psychology.
6. The Biological Practice: Outlines of a Systematics
Systematics is the study of how one ought to create a
system of biological classification and thus perform taxonomy. (“Systematics”
is not to be confused with being a “systematic philosopher.” The former term
has a technical meaning related to the theoretical foundations of animal
classification and taxonomy. The latter phrase has to do with a tightly
structured interlocking philosophical account.) In Aristotle’s logical works,
he creates a theory of definition. According to Aristotle, the best way to
create a definition is to find the proximate group in which the type of thing
resides. For example, humans are a type of thing (species) and their proximate group is animal (or blooded
animal). The proximate group is called thegenus.
Thus the genus is a larger group of which the species is merely one proper
subset. What marks off that particular species as unique? This is the differentia or the essential defining
trait. In our example with humans the differentia is “rationality.” Thus the
definition of “human” is a rational animal. “Human” is the species, “animal” is
the genus and “rationality” is the differentia.
In a similar way, Aristotle adapts his logical theory
of genus and species to biology. By thinking in terms of species and their
proximate genus, Aristotle makes a statement about the connections between
various types of animals. Aristotle does not create a full-blown classification
system that can describe all animals, but he does lay the theoretical
foundations for such.
The first overarching categories are the blooded and
the non-blooded animals. The animals covered by this distinction roughly
correspond to the modern distinction between vertebrates and invertebrates.
There are also two classes of dualizers that are animals that fit somewhat
between categories. Here is a sketch of the categorization:
I. Blooded Animals
A. Live bearing animals
1. Homo Sapiens2. Other mammals without a
distinction for primates
B. Egg-laying animals
1. Birds2. Fish
I. Non-Blooded Animals
A. Shell skinned sea animals:
testaceaB. Soft shelled sea animals: Crustacea
C. Non-shelled soft skinned sea animals:
Cephalopods
D. Insects
E. Bees
I. Dualizers (animals that share properties of
more than one group)
A. Whales, seals and porpoises—they give live
birth yet they live in the seaB. Bats—they have four appendages yet they
fly
C. Sponges—they act like both plants and like
animals
Aristotle’s proto-system of classification differs
from that of his predecessors who used habitat and other non-functional
criteria to classify animals. For example, one theory commonly set out three
large groups: air, land, and sea creatures. Because of the functional
orientation of Aristotle’s TE, Aristotle repudiates any classification system based
upon non-functional accidents. What is important is that the primary activities
of life are carried out efficiently through specially designated body parts.
Though Aristotle’s work on classification is by no
means comprehensive (but is rather a series of reflections on how to create
one), it is appropriate to describe it as meta-systematics. Such reflections
are consistent with his other key explanatory concepts of functionalism (TE and
ME) as well as his work on logic in the Organon
with respect to the utilization of genus and species. Though
incomplete, this again is a blueprint of how to construct a systematics. The
general structure of meta-systematics also acts as an independent principle
that permits Aristotle to examine animals together that are functionally
similar. Such a move enhances the reliability of analogy as a tool of
explanation.
7. “The more and the less” and “Epi to polu”
“The more and the less” is an explanatory concept that
is allied to the ME account. Principally, it is a way that individuation occurs
in the non-uniform parts. Aristotle distinguishes two sorts of parts in
animals: the uniform and the non-uniform. The uniform parts are those that if
you dumped them into a bucket and cut the bucket in half, they would still
remain the same. For example, blood is a uniform part. Dump blood into a bucket
and cut it in half and it’s still the same blood (just half the quantity). The
same is true of tissue, cartilage, tendons, skin, et al. Non-uniform parts
change when the bucket test is applied. If you dump a lung into a bucket and
cut it in half, you no longer have a proper organ. The same holds true of other
organs: heart, liver, pancreas, and so forth, as well as the skeleton (Uniform
Parts—PA 646b 20, 648b, 650a 20, 650b, 651b 20, 652a 23; Non-Uniform Parts—PA
656b 25, 622a 17, 665b 20, 683a 20, 684a 25.)
When an individual has excess nutrition (trophe), the excess (perittoma) often is distributed all
around (GA 734b 25). An external observer does not perceive the changes to the
uniform parts—except, perhaps, stomach fat. But such an observer would perceive
the difference in a child who has been well fed (whose non-uniform parts are
bigger) than one who hasn’t. The difference is accounted for by the principle
of the more and the less.
How does an external observer differentiate between
any two people? The answer is that the non-uniform parts (particularly the
skeletal structure) differ. Thus, one person’s nose is longer, another stands
taller, a third is broader in the shoulders, etc. We all have noses, stand
within a range of height and broadness of shoulders, etc. The particular mix
that we each possess makes us individuals.
Sometimes, this mix goes beyond the range of the
species (eidos). In these
instances a part becomes non-functional because it has too much material or too
little. Such situations are beyond the natural range one might expect within
the species. Because of this, the instance involved is characterized as being
unnatural (para phusin).
The possibility of unnatural events occurring in
nature affects the status of explanatory principles in biology. We remember
from above that there are two sorts of necessity: conditional and absolute. The
absolute necessity never fails. It is the sort of necessity that one can apply
to the stars that exist in the super lunar realm. One can create star charts of
the heavens that will be accurate for a thousand years forward or backward.
This is because of the mode of absolute necessity.
However, because conditional necessity depends upon
its telos, and because of the principle of the more and the less that is
non-teleologically (ME) driven, there can arise a sort of spontaneity
(cf. automaton, Phys. II.6)
that can alter the normal, expected execution of a task because spontaneity is
purposeless. In these cases the input from the material cause is greater or
lesser than is usually the case. The result is an unnatural outcome based upon
the principle of the more and the less. An example of this might be obesity.
Nourishment is delivered to the body in a hierarchical fashion beginning with
the primary needs. When all biological needs are met, then the excess goes into
hair, nails and body fat. Excess body fat can impair proper function, but not
out of design.
Because of the possibility of spontaneity and its
unintended consequences, the necessary operative in biological events
(conditional necessity) is only “for the most part” (hôs epi
to polu). We cannot expect biological explanatory principles to be
of the same order as those of the stars. Ceteris paribis principles are the best the biological realm
can give. This brute fact gives rise to a different set of epistemic
expectations than are often raised in the Prior Analytics and the Posterior Analytics. Our expectations for biology are for
general rules that are true in most cases but have many exceptions. This means
that biology cannot be an exact science, unlike astronomy. If there are always
going to be exceptions that are contrary to nature, then the biologist must do
his biology with toleration for these sorts of peripheral anomalies. This
disposition is characterized by the doctrine of epi to polu.
8. Significant Achievements and Mistakes
This section will highlight a few of Aristotle’s
biological achievements from the perspective of over 2,300 years of hindsight.
For simplicity’s sake let us break these up into “bad calls” (observations and
conclusions that have proven to be wrong) and “good calls” (observations and
conclusions that have proven to be very accurate).
We begin with the bad calls: let’s start with a few of
Aristotle’s mistakes. First, Aristotle believed that thinking occurred in the
region around the heart and not in the brain (a cooling organ, PA 652b 21-25,
cf. HA 514a 16-22). Second, Aristotle thought that men were hotter than women
(the opposite is the case). Third, Aristotle overweighed the male contribution
in reproduction. Fourth, little details are often amiss such as the number of
teeth in women. Fifth, Aristotle believed that spontaneous generation could
occur. For example, Aristotle observed that from animal dung certain flies
could appear (even though careful observation did not reveal any flies mating
and laying their eggs in the dung. The possibility of the eggs already existing
in the abdomen of the animal did not occur to Aristotle.) However, these sorts
of mistakes are more often than not the result of an a priori principle such as “women being
colder and less perfectly formed than men” or the application of his method on
(in principle) unobservables—such as human conception in which it is posited
that the male provides the efficient, formal, and final cause while the woman
provides merely the material cause.
Good Calls: Aristotle examined over 500 different
species of animals. Some species came from fishermen, hunters, farmers, and
perhaps Alexander. Many other species were viewed in nature by Aristotle. There
are some very exact observations made by Aristotle during his stay at Lesbos.
It is virtually certain that his early dissection skills were utilized solely
upon animals (due to the social prohibition on dissecting humans). One example
of this comes from the Generation of
Animals in which Aristotle breaks open fertilized chicken eggs at
carefully controlled intervals to observe when visible organs were generated.
The first organ Aristotle saw was the heart. (In fact it is the spinal cord and
the beginnings of the nervous system, but this is not visible without employing
modern staining techniques.) On eggs opened later, Aristotle saw other organs.
This led Aristotle to come out against a popular theory of conception and
development entitled, “the pre-formation theory.” In the pre-formation theory,
whose advocates extended until the eighteenth century, all the parts appear all
at once and development is merely the growth of these essential parts. The
contrary theory that Aristotle espouses is the epigenetic theory. According to
epigenesis, the parts are created in a nested hierarchical order. Thus, through
his observation, Aristotle saw that the heart was formed first, then he
postulated that other parts were formed (also backed-up by observation).
Aristotle concludes,
I mean, for instance, not that the heart once formed,
fashions the liver, and then the liver fashions something else; but that the
one is formed after the other (just as man is formed in time after a child),
not by it. The reason of this is that so far as the things formed by nature or
by human art are concerned, the formation of that which is potentially brought about by that which
is in actuality; so that the
form of B would have to be contained in A, e.g., the form of liver would have
to be in the heart—which is absurd. (GA 734a 28-35, Peck trans.)
In epigenesis the controlling process of development
operates according to the TE plan of creating the most important parts first.
Since the heart is the principle (arche)
of the body, being the center of blood production and sensation/intelligence,
it is appropriate that it should be created first. Then other parts such as the
liver, etc. are then created in their appropriate order. The
epigenesis-preformation debate lasted two thousand years and Aristotle got it
right.
Another interesting observation by Aristotle is the
discovery of the reproductive mode of the dog shark,Mustelus laevis (HA 6.10, 565b 1ff.). This species is
externally viviparous (live bearing) yet internally oviparous (egg bearing).
Such an observation could only have come from dissections and careful
observations.
Another observation concerns the reproductive habits
of cuttlefish. In this process of hectocotylization, the sperm of the Argonauta among other allied species
comes in large spermataphores that the male transfers to the mantle cavity of
the female. This complicated maneuver, described in HA 524a 4-5, 541b 9-15, cf.
544a 12, GA 720b 33, was not fully verified by moderns until 1959!
Though Aristotle’s observations on bees in HA seems to
be entirely from the beekeeper’s point of view (HA 625b7-22), he does note that
there are three classes of bees and that sexual reproduction requires that one
class give way. He begins his discussion in the Generation of Animals with the following
remark, “The generation of bees is beset with many problems” (GA 759a 9). If
there are three classes and two genders, then something is amiss. Aristotle
goes through what he feels to be all the possibilities. Though the observations
are probably second-hand, Aristotle is still able to evaluate the data. He
employs his systematic theory using the over-riding meta-principle that Nature
always acts in an orderly way (GA 760a 32) to form his explanation of the
function of each type of bee. This means that there must be a purposeful
process (TE) that guides generation. However, since neither Aristotle nor the
beekeepers had ever seen bee copulation, and since Aristotle allows for asexual
generation in some fish, he believes that the case of bees offers him another
case in which one class is sterile (complies with modern theory on worker
bees), another class creates its own kind and another (this is meant to
correspond to the Queen bee—that Aristotle calls a King Bee because it has a
stinger and females in nature never have defensive weapons), while the third
class creates not its own class but another (this is the drone).
Aristotle has got some of this right and some of it
wrong. What he has right is first, bees are unusual in having three classes.
Second, one class is infertile and works for the good of the whole. Third, one
class (the Queen) is a super-reproducer. However, in the case of bees it is
Aristotle’s method rather than his results that stirs admiration. Three meta-principles cause particular note:
- Reproduction works with two groups not three. The quickest “solution” would have been to make one group sterile and then make the other two male and female. [This would have been the correct response.] However, since none of the beekeepers reported anything like reproductive behavior among bees and because Aristotle’s own limited observations also do not note this, he is reluctant to make such a reply. It is on the basis of the phainomena that Aristotle rejects bee copulation (GA 759a 10).
- Aristotle holds that a priori argument alone is not enough. One must square the most likely explanation with the observed facts.
- Via analogy, Aristotle notes that some fish seem not to reproduce and even some flies are generated spontaneously. Thus, assigning the roles to the various classes that he does, Aristotle does not create a sui generis instance. By analogy to other suppositions of his biological theory, Aristotle is able to “solve” a troublesome case via reference to analogy. (Aristotle is also admirably cautious about his own theory, saying that more work is needed.)
What is most important in Aristotle’s accomplishments
is his combination of keen observations with a critical scientific method that
employs his systematic categories to solve problems in biology and then link
these to other issues in human life.
9. Conclusion
Since Aristotle’s biological works comprise almost a
third of his writings that have come down to us, and since these writings may
have occurred early in his career, it is very possible that the influence of
the biological works upon Aristotle’s other writings is considerable.
Aristotle’s biological works (so often neglected) should be brought to the
fore, not only in the history of biology, but also as a way of understanding
some of Aristotle’s non-biological writings.
10. References and Further Reading
a. Primary Text
- Bekker, Immanuel (ed) update by Olof Gigon , Aristotelis Opera. Berlin, Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1831-1870, rpt. W. de Gruyter, 1960-1987.
b. Key Texts in Translation
- Barnes, Jonathan (ed). The Complete Works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.
- The Clarendon Series of Aristotle:
- Balme, David (tr and ed). Updated by Allan Gotthelf, De Partibus Animalium I with De Generatione Animalium I (with passages from II 1-3). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).
- Lennox, James G. (tr and ed) Aristotle on the Parts of Animals I-4. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
- The Loeb Series of Aristotle (opposite pages of Greek and English).
c. Selected Secondary Sources
- Balme, David. “Aristotle’s Use of Differentiae in Zoology.” Aristote et les Problèms de Méthode.Louvain: Publications Universitaires 1961.
- Balme, David. “GENOS and EIDOS in Aristotle’s Biology” The Classical Quarterly. 12 (1962): 81-88.
- Balme, David. “Aristotle’s Biology was not Essentialist” Archiv Für Geschichte der Philosophie. 62.1 (1980): 1-12.
- Bourgey, Louis. Observation et Experiénce chez Aristote. Paris: J. Vrin, 1955.
- Boylan, Michael. "Mechanism and Teleology in Aristotle's Biology" Apeiron 15.2 (1981): 96-102.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Digestive and 'Circulatory' Systems in Aristotle's Biology" Journal of the History of Biology 15.1 (1982): 89-118.
- Boylan, Michael. Method and Practice in Aristotle’s Biology. Lanham, MD and London: University Press of America, 1983.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Hippocratic and Galenic Challenges to Aristotle's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 15.1 (1984): 83-112.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Place of Nature in Aristotle's Biology" Apeiron 19.1 (1985).
- Boylan, Michael. "Galen's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 19.1 (1986): 44-77.
- Boylan, Michael. "Monadic and SystemicTEleology" in Modern Problems in Teleology ed. Nicholas Rescher (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1986).
- Charles, David. Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
- Deverreux, Daniel and Pierre Pellegrin. Eds. Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote. Paris: Éditions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique,1990.
- Düring, Ingemar. Aristotles De Partibus Animalium, Critical and Literary Commentary. Goeteborg, 1943, rpt. NY.: Garland, 1980.
- Ferejohn, M. The Origins of Aristotelian Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990.
- Gotthelf, Allan and James G. Lennox, eds. Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. NY: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
- Grene, Marjorie. A Portrait of Aristotle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963.
- Joly, Robert. “La Charactérologie Antique Jusqu’ à Aristote. Revue Belge de Philologie et d’Histoire40 (1962): 5-28.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. Wissenscaft und Methode: Interpretationen zur Aristotelischen Theorie der Naturwissenschaft. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. Aristoteles und die moderne Wissenschaft Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1998.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. “Aristotles’ wissenschaftliche Methode in seinen zoologischen Schriften” in Wörhle, G., ed. Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften. Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1999, pp. 103-123.
- Kullmann, Wolfgang. “Zoologische Sammelwerk in der Antike” in Wörhle, G., ed. Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften. Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner 1999, pp. 181-198.
- Kung, Joan. “Some Aspects of Form in Aristotle’s Biology” Nature and System 2 (1980): 67-90.
- Kung, Joan. “Aristotle on Thises, Suches and the Third Man Argument” Phronesis 26 (1981): 207-247.
- Le Blonde, Jean Marie. Aristote, Philosophie de la Vie. Paris: Éditions Montaigne, 1945.
- Lesher, James. “NOUS in the Parts of Animals.” Phronesis 18 (1973): 44-68.
- Lennox, James. “Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation” Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (1982): 219-232.
- Lennox, James. “The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology” Philosophical Topics 25.1 (1999): 1-16.
- Lennox, James. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Sciences. NY: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. “Right and Left in Greek Philosophy” Journal of Hellenic Studies. 82 (1962): 67-90.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Polarity and Analogy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. “Saving the Appearances” Classical Quarterly. n.s. 28 (1978): 202-222.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Magic, Reason, and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. The Revolutions of Wisdom. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1987
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Aristotelian Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
- Louis, Pierre. “La Génération Spontanée chez Aristote” Congrèss International d’Histoire des Sciences (1968): 291-305.
- Louis, Pierre. La Découverte de la Vie. Paris: Hermann, 1975.
- Owen, G.E.L. “TITHENAI TA PHAINOMENA” Aristote et les Problèms de Méthode. Louvain, 1975.
- Owen, G.E.L. The Platonism of Aristotle. London: British Academy: Dawes Hicks Lecture on Philosophy, 1965.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. La Classification des Animaux chez Aristote: Statut de la Biologie et Unite de l’Aristotélisme. Paris: Societé d’édition “Les Belles Lettres,” 1982.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. “Logical Difference and Biological Difference: The Unity of Aristotle’s Thought” in Gotthelf, Allan and James G. Lennox, eds. Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. NY: Cambridge University Press, 1987, pp. 313-338.
- Pellegrin, Pierre. “Taxonomie, moriologie, division” in Deverreux, Daniel and Pierre Pellegrin. Eds.Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote. Paris, 1990, 37-48.
- Preus, Anthony. “Aristotle’s Parts of Animals 2.16 659b 13-19: Is it Authentic?” Classical Quarterly18.2 (1968): 170-178.
- Preus, Anthony. “Nature Uses. . . .” Apeiron 3.2 (1969): 20-33.
- Preus, Anthony. Science and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Biological Works. NY: Olhms, 1975.
- Preus, Anthony. “Eidos as Norm” Nature and System 1 (1979): 79-103.
- Solmsen, Friedrich. Aristotle’s System of the Physical World: A Comparison with his Predecessors.Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1960.
- Sorabji, Richard. Necessity, Cause, and Blame. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1980.
- Thompson, D’Arcy. Aristotle as Biologist. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1913.
- Thompson, D’Arcy. Growth and Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1917.
- Ulmer, K. Wahrheit, Kunst und Natur bei Aristotles. Tübingen: M. Niemayer, 1953.
- Witt, Charlotte. Substance and Essence in Aristotle: An Interpretation of Metaphysics VII-IX.Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989.
- Wörhle, Georg and Jochen Althoff, eds. Biologie in Geschichte der Mathematik und der Naturwissenschaften (series). Band 1 Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1999.
Author Information
Aristotle: Ethics
Standard interpretations of
Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics
usually maintain that Aristotle (384-322
B.C.E.) emphasizes the role of habit in conduct. It is commonly thought
that virtues, according to Aristotle, are habits and that the good life is a
life of mindless routine.
These interpretations of Aristotle’s ethics are the result of
imprecise translations from the ancient Greek text. Aristotle uses the
word hexis to denote moral
virtue. But the word does not merely mean passive habituation. Rather, hexis is an active condition, a state in
which something must actively hold itself.
Virtue, therefore, manifests itself in action. More
explicitly, an action counts as virtuous, according to Aristotle, when one
holds oneself in a stable equilibrium of the soul, in order to choose the
action knowingly and for its own sake. This stable equilibrium of the soul is
what constitutes character.
Similarly, Aristotle’s concept of the mean is often
misunderstood. In the Nichomachean
Ethics, Aristotle repeatedly states that virtue is a mean. The mean
is a state of clarification and apprehension in the midst of pleasures and
pains that allows one to judge what seems most truly pleasant or painful. This
active state of the soul is the condition in which all the powers of the soul
are at work in concert. Achieving good character is a process of clearing away
the obstacles that stand in the way of the full efficacy of the soul.
For Aristotle, moral virtue is the only practical road
to effective action. What the person of good character loves with right desire
and t.hinks of as an end with right reason must first be perceived as
beautiful. Hence, the virtuous person sees truly and judges rightly, since
beautiful things appear as they truly are only to a person of good character.
It is only in the middle ground between habits of acting and principles of
action that the soul can allow right desire and right reason to make their
appearance, as the direct and natural response of a free human being to
the sight of the beautiful.
Table of Contents
1. Habit
In many discussions, the word "habit" is
attached to the Ethics as
though it were the answer to a multiple-choice question on a philosophy achievement
test. Hobbes' Leviathan? Self-preservation. Descartes' Meditations? Mind-body problem.
Aristotle's Ethics? Habit.
A faculty seminar I attended a few years ago was mired in the opinion that
Aristotle thinks the good life is one of mindless routine. More recently, I
heard a lecture in which some very good things were said about Aristotle's
discussion of choice, yet the speaker still criticized him for praising habit
when so much that is important in life depends on openness and spontaneity. Can
it really be that Aristotle thought life is lived best when thinking and
choosing are eliminated?
On its face this belief makes no sense. It is partly a
confusion between an effect and one of its causes. Aristotle says that, for the
way our lives turn out, "it makes no small difference to be habituated
this way or that way straight from childhood, but an enormous difference, or
rather all the
difference." (1103b, 23-5) Is this not the same as saying those lives are
nothing but collections of habits? If this is what sticks in your memory, and
leads you to that conclusion, then the cure is easy, since habits are not the
only effects of habituation, and a thing that makes all the difference is
indispensable but not necessarily the only cause of what it produces.
We will work through this thought in a moment, but
first we need to notice that another kind of influence may be at work when you
recall what Aristotle says about habit, and another kind of medicine may be
needed against it. Are you thinking that no matter how we analyze the effects
of habituation, we will never get around the fact that Aristotle plainly says
that virtues are habits? The reply to that difficulty is that he doesn't say
that at all. He says that moral virtue is a hexis. Hippocrates Apostle, and others, translate hexis as habit, but that is not at all
what it means. The trouble, as so often in these matters, is the intrusion of
Latin. The Latin habitus
is a perfectly good translation of the Greek hexis, but if that detour gets us to habit in English we have lost our way. In
fact, a hexisis pretty
much the opposite of a habit.
The word hexis
becomes an issue in Plato's Theaetetus. Socrates makes the point that
knowledge can never be a mere passive possession, stored in the memory the way
birds can be put in cages. The word for that sort of possession, ktÎsis, is contrasted with hexis, the kind of having-and-holding
that is never passive but always at work right now. Socrates thus suggests
that, whatever knowledge is, it must have the character of a hexis in requiring the effort of
concentrating or paying attention. A hexis
is an active condition, a state in which something must actively hold itself,
and that is what Aristotle says a moral virtue is.
Some translators make Aristotle say that virtue is a
disposition, or a settled disposition. This is much better than calling it a
"habit," but still sounds too passive to capture his meaning.
In De Anima, when
Aristotle speaks of the effect produced in us by an object of sense perception,
he says this is not a disposition (diathesis)
but a hexis. (417b, 15-17)
His whole account of sensing and knowing depends on this notion that
receptivity to what is outside us depends on an active effort to hold ourselves
ready. In Book VII of the Physics, Aristotle says much the same thing about the
way children start to learn: they are not changed, he says, nor are they trained
or even acted upon in any way, but they themselves get straight into an active
state when time or adults help them settle down out of their native condition
of disorder and distraction. (247b, 17-248a, 6) Curtis Wilson once delivered a
lecture at St. John's College, in which he asked his audience to imagine what
it would be like if we had to teach children to speak by deliberately and
explicitly imparting everything they had to do. We somehow set them free to
speak, and give them a particular language to do it in, but they--Mr. Wilson
called them "little geniuses"--they do all the work.
Everyone at St. John's has thought about the kind of
learning that does not depend on the authority of the teacher and the memory of
the learner. In the Meno
it is called "recollection." Aristotle says that it is an active
knowing that is always already at work in us. In Plato's image we draw
knowledge up out of ourselves; in Aristotle's metaphor we settle down into
knowing. In neither account is it possible for anyone to train us, as Gorgias
has habituated Meno into the mannerisms of a knower. Habits can be strong but
they never go deep. Authentic knowledge does engage the soul in its depths, and
with this sort of knowing Aristotle links virtue. In the passage cited from Book
VII of the Physics, he
says that, like knowledge, virtues are not imposed on us as alterations of what
we are; that would be, he says, like saying we alter a house when we put a roof
on it. In the Categories,
knowledge and virtue are the two examples he gives of what hexis means (8b, 29); there he says that
these active states belong in the general class of dispositions, but are
distinguished by being lasting and durable. The word "disposition" by
itself he reserves for more passive states, easy to remove and change, such as
heat, cold, and sickness.
In the Ethics,
Aristotle identifies moral virtue as a hexis
in Book II, chapter 4. He confirms this identity by reviewing the kinds of
things that are in the soul, and eliminating the feelings and impulses to which
we are passive and the capacities we have by nature, but he first discovers
what sort of thing a virtue is by observing that the goodness is never in the
action but only in the doer. This is an enormous claim that pervades the whole
of the Ethics, and one that we
need to stay attentive to. No action is good or just or courageous because of
any quality in itself. Virtue manifests itself in action, Aristotle says, only
when one acts while holding oneself in a certain way. This is where the
word hexis comes into the
account, from pÙs echÙn,
the stance in which one holds oneself when acting. The indefinite adverb is
immediately explained: an action counts as virtuous when and only when one
holds oneself in a stable equilibrium of the soul, in order to choose the
action knowingly and for its own sake. I am translating as "in a stable
equilibrium" the words bebaiÙs
kai ametakinÍtÙs; the first of these adverbs means stably or after
having taken a stand, while the second does not mean rigid or immovable, but in
a condition from which one can't be moved all the way over into a different
condition. It is not some inflexible adherence to rules or duty or precedent
that is conveyed here, but something like a Newton's wheel weighted below the
center, or one of those toys that pops back upright whenever a child knocks it
over.
This stable equilibrium of the soul is what we mean by
having character. It is not the result of what we call
"conditioning." There is a story told about B. F. Skinner, the
psychologist most associated with the idea of behavior modification, that a
class of his once trained him to lecture always from one corner of the room, by
smiling and nodding whenever he approached it, but frowning and faintly shaking
their heads when he moved away from it. That is the way we acquire habits. We
slip into them unawares, or let them be imposed on us, or even impose them on
ourselves. A person with ever so many habits may still have no character.
Habits make for repetitive and predictable behavior, but character gives moral
equilibrium to a life. The difference is between a foolish consistency wholly
confined to the level of acting, and a reliability in that part of us from
which actions have their source. Different as they are, though, character and
habit sound to us like things that are linked, and in Greek they differ only by
the change of an epsilon to an eta,
making Íthos from ethos
We are finally back to Aristotle's claim that
character, Íthos, is
produced by habit, ethos.
It should now be clear though, that the habit cannot be any part of that
character, and that we must try to understand how an active condition can arise
as a consequence of a passive one, and why that active condition can only be
attained if the passive one has come first. So far we have arranged three
notions in a series, like rungs of a ladder: at the top are actives states,
such as knowledge, the moral virtues, and the combination of virtues that makes
up a character; the middle rung, the mere dispositions, we have mentioned only
in passing to claim that they are too shallow and changeable to capture the
meaning of virtue; the bottom rung is the place of the habits, and includes
biting your nails, twisting your hair, saying "like" between every
two words, and all such passive and mindless conditions. What we need to notice
now is that there is yet another rung of the ladder below the habits.
We all start out life governed by desires and
impulses. Unlike the habits, which are passive but lasting conditions, desires
and impulses are passive and momentary, but they are very strong. Listen to a
child who can't live without some object of appetite or greed, or who makes you
think you are a murderer if you try to leave her alone in a dark room. How can
such powerful influences be overcome? To expect a child to let go of the desire
or fear that grips her may seem as hopeless as Aristotle's example of training
a stone to fall upward, were it not for the fact that we all know that we have
somehow, for the most part, broken the power of these tyrannical feelings. We
don't expel them altogether, but we do get the upper hand; an adult who has
temper tantrums like those of a two-year old has to live in an institution, and
not in the adult world. But the impulses and desires don't weaken; it is rather
the case that we get stronger.
Aristotle doesn't go into much detail about how this
happens, except to say that we get the virtues by working at them: in the
give-and-take with other people, some become just, others unjust; by acting in
the face of frightening things and being habituated to be fearful or confident,
some become brave and others cowardly; and some become moderate and gentle,
others spoiled and bad-tempered, by turning around from one thing and toward
another in the midst of desires and passions. (1103 b, 1422) He sums this up by
saying that when we are at-work in a certain way, an active state results. This
innocent sentence seems to me to be one of the lynch-pins that hold together
the Ethics, the spot that
marks the transition from the language of habit to the language appropriate to
character. If you read the sentence in Greek, and have some experience of
Aristotle's other writings, you will see how loaded it is, since it says that
a hexis depends upon
an energeia. The latter
word, that can be translated as being-at-work, cannot mean mere behavior,
however repetitive and constant it may be. It is this idea of being-at-work,
which is central to all of Aristotle's thinking, that makes intelligible the
transition out of childhood and into the moral stature that comes with
character and virtue. (See Aristotle on Motion and its Place in Nature for as
discussion energeia.)
The moral life can be confused with the habits
approved by some society and imposed on its young. We at St. John's College
still stand up at the beginning and end of Friday-night lectures because
Stringfellow Barr -- one of the founders of the current curriculum -- always
stood when anyone entered or left a room. What he considered good breeding is
for us mere habit; that becomes obvious when some student who stood up at the
beginning of a lecture occasionally gets bored and leaves in the middle of it.
In such a case the politeness was just for show, and the rudeness is the truth.
Why isn't all habituation of the young of this sort? When a parent makes a
child repeatedly refrain from some desired thing, or remain in some frightening
situation, the child is beginning to act as a moderate or brave person would
act, but what is really going on within the child? I used to think that it must
be the parent's approval that was becoming stronger than the child's own
impulse, but I was persuaded by others in a study group that this alone would
be of no lasting value, and would contribute nothing to the formation of an
active state of character. What seems more likely is that parental training is
needed only for its negative effect, as a way of neutralizing the irrational
force of impulses and desires.
We all arrive on the scene already habituated, in the
habit, that is, of yielding to impulses and desires, of instantly slackening
the tension of pain or fear or unfulfilled desire in any way open to us, and
all this has become automatic in us before thinking and choosing are available
to us at all. This is a description of what is called "human nature,"
though in fact it precedes our access to our true natural state, and blocks
that access. This is why Aristotle says that "the virtues come about in us
neither by nature nor apart from nature" (1103a, 24-5). What we call
"human nature," and some philosophers call the "state of
nature," is both natural and unnatural; it is the passive part of our
natures, passively reinforced by habit. Virtue has the aspect of a second
nature, because it cannot develop first, nor by a continuous process out of our
first condition. But it is only in the moral virtues that we possess our
primary nature, that in which all our capacities can have their full
development. The sign of what is natural, for Aristotle, is pleasure, but we
have to know how to read the signs. Things pleasant by nature have no opposite
pain and no excess, because they set us free to act simply as what we are
(1154b, 15-21), and it is in this sense that Aristotle calls the life of virtue
pleasant in its own right, in itself (1099a, 6-7, 16-17). A mere habit of
acting contrary to our inclinations cannot be a virtue, by the infallible sign
that we don't like it.
Our first or childish nature is never eradicated,
though, and this is why Aristotle says that our nature is not simple, but also
has in it something different that makes our happiness assailable from within,
and makes us love change even when it is for the worse. (1154b, 21-32) But our
souls are brought nearest to harmony and into the most durable pleasures only
by the moral virtues. And the road to these virtues is nothing fancy, but is
simply what all parents begin to do who withhold some desired thing from a
child, or prevent it from running away from every irrational source of fear.
They make the child act, without virtue, as though it had virtue. It is what
Hamlet describes to his mother, during a time that is out of joint, when a son
must try to train his parent (III, Ìv,181-9):
Assume a virtue if you have it not.
That monster, custom, who all sense doth eat
Of habits evil, is angel yet in this,
That to the use of actions fair and good
He likewise gives a frock or livery,
That aptly is put on. Refrain tonight,
And that shall lend a kind of easiness
To the next abstinence; the next more easy;
For use almost can change the stamp of nature...
That monster, custom, who all sense doth eat
Of habits evil, is angel yet in this,
That to the use of actions fair and good
He likewise gives a frock or livery,
That aptly is put on. Refrain tonight,
And that shall lend a kind of easiness
To the next abstinence; the next more easy;
For use almost can change the stamp of nature...
Hamlet is talking to a middle-aged woman about lust,
but the pattern applies just as well to five-year-olds and candy. We are in a
position to see that it is not the stamp of nature that needs to be changed but
the earliest stamp of habit. We can drop Hamlet's "almost" and rid
his last quoted line of all paradox by seeing that the reason we need habit is
to change the stamp of habit. A habit of yielding to impulse can be
counteracted by an equal and opposite habit. This second habit is no virtue,
but only a mindless inhibition, an automatic repressing of all impulses. Nor do
the two opposite habits together produce virtue, but rather a state of
neutrality. Something must step into the role previously played by habit, and
Aristotle's use of the word energeia
suggests that this happens on its own, with no need for anything new to be
imposed. Habituation thus does not stifle nature, but rather lets nature make
its appearance. The description from Book VII of the Physics of the way
children begin to learn applies equally well to the way human character begins
to be formed: we settle down, out of the turmoil of childishness, into what we
are by nature.
We noticed earlier that habituation is not the end but
the beginning of the progress toward virtue. The order of states of the soul
given by Aristotle went from habit to being-at-work to the hexis or active state that can give the
soul moral stature. If the human soul had no being-at-work, no inherent and
indelible activity, there could be no such moral stature, but only customs. But
early on, when first trying to give content to the idea of happiness, Aristotle
asks if it would make sense to think that a carpenter or shoemaker has work to
do, but a human being as such is inert. His reply, of course, is that nature
has given us work to do, in default of which we are necessarily unhappy, and
that work is to put into action the power of reason. (1097b, 24-1098a, 4) Note
please that he does not say that everyone must be a philosopher, nor even that
human life is constituted by the activity of reason, but that our work is to
bring the power of logos forward into action. Later, Aristotle makes explicit
that the irrational impulses are no less human than reasoning is. (1111 b, 1-2)
His point is that, as human beings, our desires need not be mindless and
random, but can be transformed by thinking into choices, that is desires
informed by deliberation. (1113a, 11) The characteristic human way of
being-at-work is the threefold activity of seeing an end, thinking about means
to it, and choosing an action. Responsible human action depends upon the
combining of all the powers of the soul: perception, imagination, reasoning,
and desiring. These are all things that are at work in us all the time. Good
parental training does not produce them, or mold them, or alter them, but sets
them free to be effective in action. This is the way in which, according to
Aristotle, despite the contributions of parents, society, and nature, we are
the co-authors of the active states of our own souls (1114b, 23-4).
2. The Mean
Now this discussion has shown that habit does make all
the difference to our lives without being the only thing shaping those lives
and without being the final form they take. The same discussion also points to
a way to make some sense of one of the things that has always puzzled me most
in the Ethics, the
insistence that moral virtue is always in its own nature a mean condition.
Quantitative relations are so far from any serious human situation that they
would seem to be present only incidentally or metaphorically, but Aristotle
says that "by its thinghood and by the account that unfolds what it is for
it to be, virtue is a mean." (1107a, 7-8) This invites such hopeless
shallowness as in the following sentences from a recent article in the journal Ancient Philosophy (Vol. 8, pp. 101-4):
"To illustrate ...0 marks the mean (e.g. Courage); ...Cowardice is -3
while Rashness is 3...In our number language...'Always try to lower the
absolute value of your vice.' " This scholar thinks achieving courage is
like tuning in a radio station on an analog dial. Those who do not sink this
low might think instead that Aristotle is praising a kind of mediocrity, like
that found in those who used to go to college to get "gentlemen's
C's." But what sort of courage could be found in these timid souls, whose
only aim in life is to blend so well into their social surroundings that virtue
can never be chosen in preference to a fashionable vice? Aristotle points out
twice that every moral virtue is an extreme (1107a, 8-9, 22-4), but he keeps
that observation secondary to an over-riding sense in which it is a mean.
Could there be anything at all to the notion that we
hone in on a virtue from two sides? There is a wonderful image of this sort of
thing in the novel Nop's Trials
by Donald McCaig. The protagonist is not a human being, but a border collie
named Nop. The author describes the way the dog has to find the balance point,
the exact distance behind a herd of sheep from which he can drive the whole
herd forward in a coherent mass. When the dog is too close, the sheep panic and
run off in all directions; when he is too far back, the sheep ignore him, and
turn in all directions to graze. While in motion, a good working dog keeps
adjusting his pace to maintain the exact mean position that keeps the sheep
stepping lively in the direction he determines. Now working border collies are
brave, tireless, and determined. They have been documented as running more than
a hundred miles in a day, and they love their work. There is no question that
they display virtue, but it is not human virtue and not even of the same form.
Some human activities do require the long sustained tension a sheep dog is
always holding on to, an active state stretched to the limit, constantly and
anxiously kept in balance. Running on a tightrope might capture the same
flavor. But constantly maintained anxiety is not the kind of stable equilibrium
Aristotle attributes to the virtuous human soul.
I think we may have stumbled on the way that human
virtue is a mean when we found that habits were necessary in order to
counteract other habits. This does accord with the things Aristotle says about
straightening warped boards, aiming away from the worse extreme, and being on
guard against the seductions of pleasure. (1109a, 30- b9) The habit of
abstinence from bodily pleasure is at the opposite extreme from the childish
habit of yielding to every immediate desire. Alone, either of them is a vice,
according to Aristotle. The glutton, the drunkard, the person enslaved to every
sexual impulse obviously cannot ever be happy, but the opposite extremes, which
Aristotle groups together as a kind of numbness or denial of the senses (1107b,
8), miss the proper relation to bodily pleasure on the other side. It may seem
that temperance in relation to food, say, depends merely on determining how
many ounces of chocolate mousse to eat. Aristotle's example of Milo the
wrestler, who needs more food than the rest of us do to sustain him, seems to
say this, but I think that misses the point. The example is given only to show
that there is no single action that can be prescribed as right for every person
and every circumstance, and it is not strictly analogous even to temperance
with respect to food. What is at stake is not a correct quantity of food but a
right relation to the pleasure that comes from eating.
Suppose you have carefully saved a bowl of chocolate
mousse all day for your mid-evening snack, and just as you are ready to treat
yourself, a friend arrives unexpectedly to visit. If you are a glutton, you
might hide the mousse until the friend leaves, or gobble it down before you
open the door. If you have the opposite vice, and have puritanically suppressed
in yourself all indulgence in the pleasures of food, you probably won't have
chocolate mousse or any other treat to offer your visitor. If the state of your
soul is in the mean in these matters, you are neither enslaved to nor shut out
from the pleasure of eating treats, and can enhance the visit of a friend by
sharing them. What you are sharing is incidentally the 6 ounces of chocolate
mousse; the point is that you are sharing the pleasure, which is not found on
any scale of measurement. If the pleasures of the body master you, or if you
have broken their power only by rooting them out, you have missed out on the
natural role that such pleasures can play in life. In the mean between those
two states, you are free to notice possibilities that serve good ends, and to
act on them.
It is worth repeating that the mean is not the 3
ounces of mousse on which you settled, since if two friends had come to visit
you would have been willing to eat 2 ounces. That would not have been a
division of the food but a multiplication of the pleasure. What is enlightening
about the example is how readily and how nearly universally we all see that
sharing the treat is the right thing to do. This is a matter of immediate
perception, but it is perception of a special kind, not that of any one of the
five senses, Aristotle says, but the sort by which we perceive that a triangle
is the last kind of figure into which a polygon can be divided. (1142a, 28-30)
This is thoughtful and imaginative perceiving, but it has to be perceived. The
childish sort of habit clouds our sight, but the liberating counter-habit
clears that sight. This is why Aristotle says that the person of moral stature,
the spoudaios, is the one to
whom things appear as they truly are. (1113a, 30-1) Once the earliest habits
are neutralized, our desires are disentangled from the pressure for immediate
gratification, we are calm enough to think, and most important, we can see what
is in front of us in all its possibility. The mean state here is not a point on
a dial that we need to fiddle up and down; it is a clearing in the midst of
pleasures and pains that lets us judge what seems most truly pleasant and
painful.
Achieving temperance toward bodily pleasures is, by
this account, finding a mean, but it is not a simple question of adjusting a
single varying condition toward the more or the less. The person who is always
fighting the same battle, always struggling like the sheep dog to maintain the
balance point between too much and too little indulgence, does not, according
to Aristotle, have the virtue of temperance, but is at best selfrestrained or continent. In that case, the reasoning
part of the soul is keeping the impulses reined in. But those impulses can slip
the reins and go their own way, as parts of the body do in people with certain
disorders of the nerves. (1102b, 14-22) Control in self-restrained people is an
anxious, unstable equilibrium that will lapse whenever vigilance is relaxed. It
is the old story of the conflict between the head and the emotions, never
resolved but subject to truces. A soul with separate, self-contained rational
and irrational parts could never become one undivided human being, since the
parties would always believe they had divergent interests, and could at best
compromise. The virtuous soul, on the contrary, blends all its parts in the act
of choice.
This is arguably the best way to understand the active
state of the soul that constitutes moral
virtue and forms character. It is the condition in which all the
powers of the soul are at work together, making it possible for action to
engage the whole human being. The work of achieving character is a process of
clearing away the obstacles that stand in the way of the full efficacy of the
soul. Someone who is partial to food or drink, or to running away from trouble
or to looking for trouble, is a partial human being. Let the whole power of the
soul have its influence, and the choices that result will have the
characteristic look that we call "courage" or "temperance"
or simply "virtue." Now this adjective "characteristic"
comes from the Greek word charactÍr,
which means the distinctive mark scratched or stamped on anything, and which is
apparently never used in the Nicomachean
Ethics. In the sense of character of which we are speaking, the
word for which is Íthos,
we see an outline of the human form itself. A person of character is someone
you can count on, because there is a human nature in a deeper sense than that
which refers to our early state of weakness. Someone with character has taken a
stand in that fully mature nature, and cannot be moved all the way out of it.
But there is also such a thing as bad character, and
this is what Aristotle means by vice,
as distinct from bad habits or weakness. It is possible for someone with full responsibility and the free use
of intellect to choose always to yield to bodily pleasure or to greed. Virtue
is a mean, first because it can only emerge out of the stand-off between
opposite habits, but second because it chooses to take its stand not in either
of those habits but between them. In this middle region, thinking does come
into play, but it is not correct to say that virtue takes its stand in
principle; Aristotle makes clear that vice is a principled choice that
following some extreme path toward or away from pleasure is right. (1146b,
22-3) Principles are wonderful things, but there are too many of them, and
exclusive adherence to any one of them is always a vice.
In our earlier example, the true glutton would be
someone who does not just have a bad habit of always indulging the desire for
food, but someone who has chosen on principle that one ought always to yield to
it. In Plato's Gorgias,
Callicles argues just that, about food, drink, and sex. He is serious, even
though he is young and still open to argument. But the only principled
alternative he can conceive is the denial of the body, and the choice of a life
fit only for stones or corpses. (492E) This is the way most attempts to be
serious about right action go astray. What, for example, is the virtue of a
seminar leader? Is it to ask appropriate questions but never state an opinion?
Or is it to offer everything one has learned on the subject of discussion? What
principle should rule?--that all learning must come from the learners, or that
without prior instruction no useful learning can take place? Is there a hybrid
principle? Or should one try to find the mid-way point between the opposite
principles? Or is the virtue some third kind of thing altogether?
Just as habits of indulgence always stand opposed to
habits of abstinence, so too does every principle of action have its opposite
principle. If good habituation ensures that we are not swept away by our
strongest impulses, and the exercise of intelligence ensures that we will see
two worthy sides to every question about action, what governs the choice of the
mean? Aristotle gives this answer: "such things are among particulars, and
the judgment is in the act of sense-perception." (1109b, 23-4) But this is
the calmly energetic, thought-laden perception to which we referred earlier.
The origin of virtuous action is neither intellect nor appetite, but is
variously described as intellect through-and-through infused with appetite, or
appetite wholly infused with thinking, or appetite and reason joined for the
sake of something; this unitary source is called by Aristotle simply anthropos. (1139a, 34, b, S-7) But our
thinking must contribute right
reason (ho orthos logos)
and our appetites must contribute rightdesire
(hÍ orthÍ orexis) if the action
is to have moral stature. (1114b, 29, 1139a, 24-6, 31-2) What makes them right
can only be the something for the sake of which they unite, and this is what is
said to be accessible only to sense perception. This brings us to the third
word we need to think about.
3. Noble
Aristotle says plainly and repeatedly what it is that
moral virtue is for the sake of, but the translators are afraid to give it to
you straight. Most of them say it is the noble.
One of them says it is the fine.
If these answers went past you without even registering, that is probably
because they make so little sense. To us, the word "noble" probably
connotes some sort of high-minded naiveté, something hopelessly impractical.
But Aristotle considers moral virtue the only practical road to effective
action. The word "fine" is of the same sort but worse, suggesting
some flimsy artistic soul who couldn't endure rough treatment, while Aristotle
describes moral virtue as the most stable and durable condition in which we can
meet all obstacles. The word the translators are afraid of is to kalon, the beautiful. Aristotle
singles out as the distinguishing mark of courage, for example, that it is
always "for the sake of the beautiful, for this is the end of
virtue." (111 S b, 12-13) Of magnificence, or large-scale philanthropy, he
says it is "for the sake of the beautiful, for this is common to the
virtues." (1122 b, 78) What the person of good character loves with right
desire and thinks of as an end with right reason must first be perceived as
beautiful.
The Loeb translator explains why he does not use the
word "beautiful" in the Nicomachean
Ethics. He tells us to
kalon has two different uses, and refers both to "(1) bodies
well shaped and works of art ...well made, and (2) actions well done." (p.
6) But we have already noticed that Aristotle says the judgment of what is
morally right belongs to sense-perception. And he explicitly compares the well
made work of art to an act that springs from moral virtue. Of the former,
people say that it is not possible add anything to it or take anything from it,
and Aristotle says that virtue differs from art in that respect only in being
more precise and better. (1106b, 10-15) An action is right in the same way a
painting might get everything just right. Antigone contemplates in her
imagination the act of burying her brother, and says "it would be a
beautiful thing to die doing this." (Antigone,
line 72) This is called "courage." Neoptolemus stops Philoctetes from
killing Odysseus with the bow he has just returned, and says "neither for
me nor for you is this a beautiful thing." (Philoctetes, line 1304) This is a recognition that the
rightness of returning the bow would be spoiled if it were used for revenge.
This is not some special usage of the Greek language, but one that speaks to us
directly, if the translators let it. And it is not a kind of language that
belongs only to poetic tragedy, since the tragedians find their subjects by
recognizing human virtue in circumstances that are most hostile to it.
In the most ordinary circumstances, any mother might
say to a misbehaving child, in plain English, "don't be so ugly." And
any of us, parent, friend, or grudging enemy, might on occasion say to someone
else, "that was a beautiful thing you did." Is it by some wild
coincidence that twentieth-century English and fourth-century BC Greek link the
same pair of uses under one word? Aristotle is always alert to the natural way
that important words have more than one meaning. The inquiry in his Metaphysics is built around the
progressive narrowing of the word "being" until its primary meaning
is discovered. In the Physics the various senses of motion and change are
played on like the keyboard of a piano, and serve to uncover the double source
of natural activity. The inquiry into ethics is not built in this fashion;
Aristotle asks about the way the various meanings of the good are organized,
but he immediately drops the question, as being more at home in another sort of
philosophic inquiry. (1096b, 26-32) It is widely claimed that Aristotle says
there is no good itself, or any other form at all of the sort spoken of in
Plato's dialogues. This is a misreading of any text of Aristotle to which it is
referred. Here in the study of ethics it is a failure to see that the idea of
the good is not rejected simply, but only held off as a question that does not
arise as first for us. Aristotle praises Plato for understanding that
philosophy does not argue from first principles but toward them. (1095a, 31-3)
But while Aristotle does not make the meanings of the
good an explicit theme that shapes his inquiry, he nevertheless does plainly
lay out its three highest senses, and does narrow down the three into two and
indirectly into one. He tells us there are three kinds of good toward which our
choices look, the pleasant, the beautiful, and the beneficial or advantageous.
(1104b, 31-2) The last of these is clearly subordinate to the other two, and
when the same issue comes up next, it has dropped out of the list. The goods
sought for their own sake are said to be of only two kinds, the pleasant and
the beautiful. (1110b, 9-12) That the beautiful is the primary sense of the
good is less obvious, both because the pleasant is itself resolved into a
variety of senses, and because a whole side of virtue that we are not
considering in this lecture aims at the true, but we can sketch out some ways
in which the beautiful emerges as the end of human action.
Aristotle's first description of moral virtue required
that the one acting choose an action knowingly, out of a stable equilibrium of
the soul, and for its own sake. The knowing in question turned out to be
perceiving things as they are, as a result of the habituation that clears our
sight. The stability turned out to come from the active condition of all the
powers of the soul, in the mean position opened up by that same habituation,
since it neutralized an earlier, opposite, and passive habituation to
self-indulgence. In the accounts of the particular moral virtues, an action's
being chosen for its own sake is again and again specified as meaning chosen
for no reason other than that it is beautiful. In Book III, chapter 8,
Aristotle refuses to give the name courageous to anyone who acts bravely for
the sake of honor, out of shame, from experience that the danger is not as
great as it seems, out of spiritedness or anger or the desire for revenge, or
from optimism or ignorance. Genuinely courageous action is in no obvious way
pleasant, and is not chosen for that reason, but there is according to Aristotle
a truer pleasure inherent in it. It doesn't need pleasure dangled in front of
it as an extra added attraction. Lasting and satisfying pleasure never comes to
those who seek pleasure, but only to the philokalos, who looks past pleasure to the beautiful.
(1099a, 15-17, 13)
In our earlier example of temperance, I think most of
us would readily agree that the one who had his eye only the chocolate mousse
found less pleasure than the one who saw that it would be a better thing to
share it. And Aristotle does say explicitly that the target the temperate
person looks to is the beautiful. (1119b, 15-17) But since there are three
primary moral virtues, courage, temperance, and justice, it is surprising that
in the whole of Book V, which discusses justice, Aristotle never mentions the
beautiful. It must somehow be applicable, since he says it is common to all the
moral virtues, but in that case it would seem that the account of justice could
not be complete if it is not connected to the beautiful. I think this does
happen, but in an unexpected way.
Justice seems to be not only a moral virtue, but in
some pre-eminent way the
moral virtue. And Aristotle says that there is a sense of the word in which the
one we call "just" is the person who has all moral virtue, insofar as
it affects other people. (1129b, 26-7) In spite of all this, I believe that
Aristotle treats justice as something inherently inadequate, a condition of the
soul that cannot ever achieve the end at which it aims. Justice concerns itself
with the right distribution of rewards and punishments within a community. This
would seem to be the chief aim of the lawmakers, but Aristotle says that they
do not take justice as seriously as friendship. They accord friendship a higher
moral stature than justice. (1155a, 23-4) It seems to me now that Aristotle
does too, and that the discussion of friendship in Books VIII and IX replaces
that of justice.
What is the purpose of reward and punishment? I take
Aristotle's answer to be homonoia,
the like-mindedness that allows a community to act in concord. For the sake of
this end, he says, it is not good enough that people be just, while if they are
friends they have no need to be just: (1155a, 24-9) So far, this sounds as
though friendship is merely something advantageous for the social or political
good, but Aristotle immediately adds that it is also beautiful. The whole
account of friendship, you will recall, is structured around the threefold
meaning of the good. Friendships are distinguished as being for use, for pleasure,
or for love of the friend's character.
Repeatedly, after raising questions about the highest
kind of friendship, Aristotle resolves them by looking to the beautiful: it is
a beautiful thing to do favors for someone freely, without expecting a return (1163a,
1, 1168a, 10-13); even in cases of urgent necessity, when there is a choice
about whom to benefit, one should first decide whether the scale tips toward
the necessary or the beautiful thing (1165a, 4-5 ); to use money to support our
parents is always more beautiful than to use it for ourselves (1165a, 22-4);
someone who strives to achieve the beautiful in action would never be accused
of being selfish (1168b, 25-8). These observations culminate in the claim that,
"if all people competed for the beautiful, and strained to do the most
beautiful things, everything people need in common, and the greatest good for
each in particular, would be achieved ...for the person of moral stature will
forego money, honor, and all the good things people fight over to achieve the
beautiful for himself." (1169a, 8-11, 20-22) This does not mean that
people can do without such things as money and honor, but that the distribution
of such things takes care of itself when people take each other seriously and
look to something higher.
The description of the role of the beautiful in moral
virtue is most explicit in the discussion of courage, where the emphasis is on
the great variety of things that resemble courage but fail to achieve it
because they are not solely for the sake of the beautiful. That discussion is
therefore mostly negative. We can now see that the discussion of justice was
also of a negative character, since justice itself resembles the moral virtue
called "friendship" without achieving it, again because it does not
govern its action by looking to the beautiful. The discussion of friendship
contains the largest collection of positive examples of actions that are
beautiful. There is something of a tragic feeling to the account of courage,
pointing to the extreme situation of war in which nothing might be left to
choose but a beautiful death. But the account of friendship points to the
healthy community, in which civil war and other conflicts are driven away by
the choice of what is beautiful in life. (1155a, 24-7) By the end of the ninth
book, there is no doubt that Aristotle does indeed believe in a primary sense
of the good, at least in the human realm, and that the name of this highest
good is the beautiful.
And it should be noticed that the beautiful is at work
not only in the human realm. In De
Anima, Aristotle argues that, while the soul moves itself in the
act of choice, the ultimate source of its motion is the practical good toward
which it looks, which causes motion while it is itself motionless. (433a, 29-30,
b, 11-13) This structure of the motionless first mover is taken up in Book XII
of the Metaphysics, where
Aristotle argues that the order of the cosmos depends on such a source, which
causes motion in the manner of something loved; he calls this source, as one of
its names, "the beautiful," that which is beautiful not in seeming
but in being. (1072a, 26-b, 4) Like Diotima in Plato's Symposium, Aristotle makes the beautiful
the good itself.
A final word, on the fact that the beautiful in
the Ethics is not an
object of contemplation simply, but the source of action: In an article on
the Poetics, I discussed the intimate
connection of beauty with the experience of wonder. The sense of wonder seems
to be the way of seeing which allows things to appear as what they are, since
it holds off our tendencies to make things fit into theories or opinions we
already hold, or use things for purposes that have nothing to do with them. But
this is what Aristotle says repeatedly is the ultimate effect of moral virtue,
that the one who has it sees truly and judges rightly, since only to someone of
good character do the things that are beautiful appear as they truly are (1113
a, 29-35), that practical wisdom depends on moral virtue to make its aim right
(1144a, 7-9), and that the eye of the soul that sees what is beautiful as the
end or highest good of action gains its active state only with moral virtue
(1144a, 26-33). It is only in the middle ground between habits of acting and between
principles of action that the soul can allow right desire and right reason to
make their appearance, as the direct and natural response of a free human being
to the sight of the beautiful.
4. References and Further Reading
- Aristotle, Metaphysics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Green Lion Press, 1999.
- Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Focus Philosophical Library, Pullins Press, 2002.
- Aristotle, On the Soul, Joe Sachs (trans.), Green Lion Press, 2001.
- Aristotle, Poetics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Focus Philosophical Library, Pullins Press, 2006.
- Aristotle, Physics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Rutgers U. P., 1995.
Author Information
Aristotle: Logic
Aristotelian logic, after a
great and early triumph, consolidated its position of influence to rule over
the philosophical world throughout the Middle Ages up until the 19th
Century. All that changed in a hurry when modern logicians embraced a new
kind of mathematical logic and pushed out what they regarded as the antiquated
and clunky method of syllogisms. Although Aristotle’s very rich and
expansive account of logic differs in key ways from modern approaches, it is
more than a historical curiosity. It provides an alternative way of
approaching logic and continues to provide critical insights into contemporary
issues and concerns. The main thrust of this article is to explain
Aristotle’s logical system as a whole while correcting some prominent
misconceptions that persist in the popular understanding and even in some of
the specialized literature. Before getting down to business, it is
important to point out that Aristotle is a synoptic thinker with an
over-arching theory that ties together all aspects and fields of
philosophy. He does not view logic as a separate, self-sufficient
subject-matter, to be considered in isolation from other aspects of disciplined
inquiry. Although we cannot consider all the details of his encyclopedic
approach, we can sketch out the larger picture in a way that illuminates the
general thrust of his system. For the purposes of this entry, let us
define logic as that field of inquiry which investigates how we reason
correctly (and, by extension, how we reason incorrectly). Aristotle does
not believe that the purpose of logic is to prove that human beings can have
knowledge. (He dismisses excessive scepticism.) The aim of logic is
the elaboration of a coherent system that allows us to investigate, classify,
and evaluate good and bad forms of reasoning.
Table of Contents
- The Organon
- Categories
- From Words into Propositions
- Kinds of Propositions
- Square of Opposition
- Laws of Thought
- Existential Assumptions
- Form versus Content
- The Syllogism
- Inductive Syllogism
- Deduction versus Induction
- Science
- Non-Discursive Reasoning
- Rhetoric
- Fallacies
- Moral Reasoning
- References and Further Reading
1. The Organon
To those used to the silver tones of an accomplished
writer like Plato, Aristotle’s prose will seem, at first glance, a difficult
read. What we have are largely notes, written at various points in his
career, for different purposes, edited and cobbled together by later
followers. The style of the resulting collection is often rambling,
repetitious, obscure, and disjointed. There are many arcane, puzzling,
and perhaps contradictory passages. This problem is compounded by the
abstract, technical vocabulary logic sometimes requires and by the wide-ranging
scope and the scattered nature of Aristotle’s observations. Some
familiarity with Greek terminology is required if one hopes to capture the
nuances in his thought. Classicists and scholars do argue, of course,
about the precise Greek meaning of key words or phrases but many of these
debates involve minor points of interpretation that cannot concern us
here. Aristotle’s logical vocabulary needs to be understood within the
larger context of his system as a whole. Many good translations of
Aristotle are available. (Parenthetical citations below include the
approximate Bekker number (the scholarly notation for referring to Aristotelian
passages according to page, column, and line number of a standard edition), the
English title of the work, and the name of the translator.)
Ancient commentators regarded logic as a
widely-applicable instrument or method for careful thinking. They grouped
Aristotle’s six logical treatises into a sort of manual they called the Organon (Greek for “tool”). The Organon included the Categories, On Interpretation, the Prior
Analytics, the Posterior
Analytics, the Topics,
and On Sophistical Refutations.
These books touch on many issues: the logical structure of propositions, the
proper structure of arguments (syllogisms), the difference between induction
and deduction, the nature of scientific knowledge, basic fallacies (forms of specious reasoning), debating techniques,
and so on. But we cannot confine our present investigations to the Organon. Aristotle comments on the
principle of non-contradiction in the Metaphysics,
on less rigorous forms of argument in the Rhetoric,
on the intellectual virtues in the Nicomachean
Ethics, on the difference between truth and falsity in On the Soul, and so on. We cannot
overlook such important passages if we wish to gain an adequate understanding
of Aristotelian logic.
2. Categories
The world, as Aristotle describes it in his Categories, is composed of
substances—separate, individual things—to which various characterizations or
properties can be ascribed. Each substance is a unified whole composed of
interlocking parts. There are two kinds of substances. A primary substance is (in the simplest
instance) an independent (or detachable) object, composed of matter,
characterized by form. Individual living organisms—a man, a rainbow
trout, an oak tree—provide the most unambiguous examples of primary
substances. Secondary substances
are the larger groups, the species or genera, to which these individual
organisms belong. So man, horse, mammals, animals (and so on) would be
examples of secondary substances. As we shall see, Aristotle’s logic is
about correctly attributing specific properties to secondary substances (and
therefore, indirectly, about attributing these properties to primary substances
or individual things).
Aristotle elaborates a logic that is designed to
describe what exists in the world. We may well wonder then, how many
different ways can we describe something? In his Categories (4.1b25-2a4), Aristotle enumerates ten different ways
of describing something. These categories (Greek=kategoria, deriving from the verb to
indicate, signify) include (1) substance, (2) quantity, (3) quality, (4)
relation, (5) where, (6) when, (7) being-in-a-position, (8) possessing, (9)
doing or (10) undergoing something or being affected by something. In the
Topics (I.9, 103b20-25), he
includes the same list, replacing “substance” (ousia) with “essence” (ti
esti). We can, along with Aristotle, give an example of each
kind of description: (1) to designate something as a “horse” or a “man” is to
identify it as a substance or to attribute an essence to it; (2) to say that
the wall is four feet long is to describe it in terms of quantity; (3) to say
that the roof is “white” is to ascribe a quality to it; (4) to say that
your weight is “double” mine is to describe a relation between the two; (5) to
say something happened in the market-place is to explain where; (6) to say it
happened last year is to explain when; (7) to say an old man is sitting is to
describe his position; (8) to say the girl has shoes on is to describe what she
possesses; (9) to say the head chef is cutting a carrot with a knife is to
describe what he is doing; and finally, (10) to say wood is being burned in the
fireplace is to describe what it means for the wood to undergo burning or to be
affected by fire. Commentators claim that these ten categories represent
either different descriptions of being or different kinds of being. (To
be a substance is to be in a
certain way; to possess quantity is to be in
a certain way; to possess a quality is to be
in a certain way, and so on.) There is nothing magical about
the number ten. Aristotle gives shorter lists elsewhere. (Compare Posterior Analytics, I.22.83a22-24, where
he lists seven predications, for example). Whether Aristotle intends the
longer lists as a complete enumeration of all conceivable types of descriptions
is an open question. Scholars have noticed that the first category,
substance or essence, seems to be fundamentally different than the others; it
is what something is in the most complete and perfect way.
3. From Words into Propositions
Aristotle does not believe that all reasoning deals
with words. (Moral decision-making is, for Aristotle, a form of reasoning
that can occur without words.) Still, words are a good place to begin our
study of his logic. Logic, as we now understand it, chiefly has to do
with how we evaluate arguments. But arguments are made of statements,
which are, in turn, made of words. In Aristotelian logic, the most basic
statement is a proposition, a complete sentence that asserts something. (There
are other kinds of sentences—prayers, questions, commands—that do not assert
anything true or false about the world and which, therefore, exist outside the
purview of logic.) A proposition is ideally composed of at least three
words: a subject (a word naming
a substance), a predicate (a
word naming a property), and a connecting verb, what logicians call a copula (Latin, for “bond” or “connection”). Consider the
simple statement: “Socrates is wise.” Socrates is the subject; the
property of being wise is the predicate, and the verb “is” (the copula) links Socrates and wisdom
together in a single affirmation. We can express all this symbolically as
“S is P” where “S” stands for the subject “Socrates” and “P” stands for the
predicate “being wise.” The sentence “Socrates is wise” (or symbolically,
“S is P”) qualifies as a proposition; it is a statement that claims that
something is true about the world. Paradigmatically, the subject would be
a (secondary) substance (a natural division of primary substances) and the
predicate would be a necessary or essential property as in: “birds are
feathered,” or “triangles have interior angles equal to two right angles,” or
“fire is upward-moving.” But any overly restrictive metaphysical idea
about what terms in a proposition mean seems to unnecessarily restrict
intelligent discourse. Suppose someone were to claim that “anger is
unethical.” But anger is not a substance; it is a property of a substance
(an organism). Still, it makes perfect sense to predicate properties of
anger. We can say that anger is unethical, hard to control, an excess of
passion, familiar enough, and so on. Aristotle himself exhibits some
flexibility here. Still, there is something to Aristotle’s view that the
closer a proposition is to the metaphysical structure of the world, the more it
counts as knowledge. Aristotle has an all-embracing view of logic and yet
believes that, what we could call “metaphysical correctness” produces a more
rigorous, scientific form of logical expression.
Of course, it is not enough to produce propositions;
what we are after is true
propositions. Aristotle believes that only propositions are true or
false. Truth or falsity (at least with respect to linguistic expression)
is a matter of combining words into complete propositions that purport to
assert something about the world. Individual words or incomplete phrases,
considered by themselves, are neither true or false. To say, “Socrates,”
or “jumping up and down,” or “brilliant red” is not to assert anything true or
false about the world. It is to repeat words without making any claim
about the way things are. In the Metaphysics,
Aristotle provides his own definition of true and false: “to say of what is
that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true”; and “to say of what is
that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false.” (IV.7.1011b25,
Ross.) In other words, a true proposition corresponds to way things are. But Aristotle is not
proposing a correspondence theory of truth as an expert would understand
it. He is operating at a more basic level. Consider the statement:
“Spiders have eight legs.” (Symbolically, “All S is P,” where S, the
subject, is “spiders”; P, the predicate, is “the state of being eight-legged,”
and the verb “is” functions as the copula.)
What does it mean to say that this claim is true? If we observe spiders
to discover how many legs they have, we will find that (except in a few odd
cases) spiders do have eight legs, so the proposition will be true because what
it says matches reality. As we shall see, Aristotle’s logic is designed
to produce just this kind of general statement.
4. Kinds of Propositions
Aristotle suggests that all propositions must either
affirm or deny something. Every proposition must be either an affirmation
or a negation; it cannot be both. He also points out that propositions
can make claims about what necessarily
is the case, about what possibly
is the case, or even about what is impossible.
His modal logic, which deals with these further qualifications about
possibility or necessity, presents difficulties of interpretation. We
will focus on his assertoric (or non-modal) logic here. Still, many of
Aristotle’s points about necessity and possibility seem highly intuitive.
In one famous example about a hypothetical sea battle, he observes that the
necessary truth of a mere proposition does not trump the uncertainty of future
events. Because it is necessarily true that there will be or will not be
a sea battle tomorrow, we cannot conclude that either alternative is
necessarily true. (De Interpretatione,
9.19a30ff.) So the necessity that attaches to the proposition “there will
or will not be a sea battle tomorrow” does not transfer over to the claim ‘that
there will be a sea battle tomorrow” or to the claim “there will not be a sea
battle tomorrow.” Aristotle goes out of his way to emphasize the point
that our personal beliefs about what will happen in the future do not determine
whether the individual propositions are true. (Note that we must not
confuse the necessary truth of a proposition with the necessity that
precipitates the conclusion of a deductively-valid argument. The former is
sometimes called “material,” “non-logical,” or “metaphysical” necessity; the
later, “formal,” “deductive,” or “logical” necessity.” We discuss these
issues further below.)
Aristotle claims that all propositions can be expressed
using the “Subject copula
Predicate” formula and that complex propositions are, on closer inspection,
collections of simpler claims that display, in turn, this fundamental
structure. Having fixed the proper logical form of a proposition, he goes
on to classify different kinds of propositions. He begins by
distinguishing between particular terms and universal terms. (The term he
uses for “universal” is the Greek “katholou.”)
Particular terms refer to individual things; universal terms refer to groups of
things. The name “Socrates” is a particular term because it refers to a
single human being; the word “spiders” is a universal term for it universally applies to all members of the
group “spiders.” Aristotle realizes, of course, that universal terms may
be used to refer to parts of a group as well as to entire groups. We may
claim that all spiders have
eight legs or that only some
spiders have book-lungs. In the first case, a property, eight-leggedness,
is predicated of the entire group referred to by the universal term; in the
second case, the property of having book-lungs is predicated of only part of
the group. So, to use Aristotelian language, one may predicate a property
universally or not universally of the group referred to by a universal term.
This brings us to Aristotle’s classification of the
four different kinds of categorical propositions (called “categorical
propositions” because they assert a relationship between two categories or
kinds). Each different categorical proposition possesses quantity insomuch as it represents a
universal or a particular predication (referring to all or only some members of
the subject class). It also possesses a definite quality (positive or negative) insomuch as it affirms or denies the specified
predication. The adjectives “all,” “no,” and “some” (which is understood
as meaning “at least one”) determine the quantity of the proposition; the
quality is determined by whether the verb is in the affirmative or the
negative. Rather than going into the details of Aristotle’s original
texts, suffice it to say that contemporary logicians generally distinguish
between four logical possibilities:
1. Universal Affirmation: All S are P
(called A statements from the Latin, “AFFIRMO”:
I affirm).
2. Universal Negation: No S are P
(called E statements from “NEGO”:
I deny).
3. Particular Affirmation: Some S are P
(called I statements from AFFIRMO).
4. Particular Negation: Some S are not P
(called O statements from NEGO).
Note that these four possibilities are not, in every
instance, mutually exclusive. As mentioned above, particular statements
using the modifier “some” refer to at least
one member of a
group. To say that “some S are P” is to say that “at least one S is P”;
to say that “some S are not P” is to say that “at least one S is not P.” It
must follow then (at least on Aristotle’s system) that universal statements
require the corresponding particular statement. If “All S are P,” at
least one S must be P; that is, the particular statement “Some S are P” must be
true. Again, if “No S are P,” at least one S must not be P; that is, the
particular statement “Some S are not P” must be true. (More on this, with
qualifications, below.) Note also that Aristotle treats propositions with
an individual subject such as “Socrates is wise” as universal propositions (as
if the proposition was saying something like “all instances of Socrates” are
wise.) One caveat: Although we cannot linger on further
complications here, keep in mind that this is not the only way to divide up
logical possibility.
5. Square of Opposition
Aristotle examines the way in which these four
different categorical propositions are related to one another. His views
have come down to us as “the square of opposition,” a mnemonic diagram that
captures, systematizes, and slightly extends what Aristotle says in De Interpretatione. (Cf. 6.17a25ff.)
Figure 1
The Traditional Square of Opposition
As it turns out, we can use a square with crossed
interior diagonals (Fig. 1 above) to identify four kinds of relationships that
hold between different pairs of categorical propositions. Consider each
relationship in turn.
1) Contradictory
propositions possess opposite truth-values. In the diagram,
they are linked by a diagonal line. If one of two contradictories is
true, the other must be false, and vice versa. So the A proposition (All
S are P) and the O proposition (Some S are not P) are contradictories. Clearly,
if it is true that “all S are P,” then the O statement that “some S are not P”
must be false. And if it is true that “some S are not P,” then the A
statement that “all S are P” must be false. The same relationship holds
between E (No S are P) and I (Some S are P) propositions. To use a simple
example: If it is true that “all birds lay eggs,” then it must be false that
“some birds do not lay eggs.” And if it is true that “some birds do not
fly,” then it must be false that “all birds fly.”
2) Contrary propositions cannot both be
true. The top horizontal line in the square joining the A proposition
(All S are P) to the E proposition (No S are P) represents this logical
relationship. Clearly, it cannot be true that “all S are P” and that “no
S are P.” The truth of one of these contrary propositions excludes the
truth of the other. It is possible, however, that both statements are
false as in the case where some S are P and some (other) S are not P. So,
for example, the statements “all politicians tell lies” and “no politicians
tell lies” cannot both be true. They will, however, both be false if it
is indeed the case that some
politicians tell lies whereas some
do not.
3) The relationship of subalternation results when the truth of
a universal proposition, “the superaltern,” requires the truth of a second
particular proposition, “the subaltern.” The vertical lines moving
downward from the top to the bottom of the square in the diagram represent this
condition. Clearly, if all members of an existent group possess (or do
not possess) a specific characteristic, it must follow that any smaller subset
of that group must possess (or not possess) that specific characteristic.
If the A proposition (All S are P) is true, it must follow that the I
proposition (“Some S are P”) must be true. Again, if the E proposition
(No S are P) is true, it must follow that the O proposition (Some S are not P)
must be true. Consider, for example, the statement, “all cheetahs are
fast.” If every member of the whole group of cheetahs is fast, then it
must be the case that at least one member of the group of cheetahs is fast;
that is, the statement “some cheetahs are fast” must be true. And, to
reformulate the same example as a negation, if it is true that “no cheetahs are
slow,” then it must be the case that at least one member of the group of
cheetahs is not slow; that is, the statement “some cheetahs are not slow” must
be true.
Note that subalternation does not work in the opposite
direction. If “Some S are P,” it need not follow that “All S are
P.” And if “Some S are not P,” it need not follow that “No S are
P.” We should also point out that if the subaltern is false, it must follow
that the superaltern is false. If it is false to say that “Some S are P,”
it must be false to say that “All S are P.” And if it is false to say
that “Some S are not P,” it must be false to say that “No S are P.”
4) Subcontrary
propositions cannot both be false. The bottom horizontal line in the
square joining the I proposition (Some S are P) to the O proposition (Some S
are not P) represents this kind of subcontrary relationship. Keeping to
the assumptions implicit in Aristotle’s system, there are only three
possibilities: (1) All S have property P; in which case, it must also be true
(by subalternation) that “some S are P.” (2) No S have property P; in
which case it must also be true (by subalternation) that “some S are not
P.” (3) Some S have and some S do not have property P; in which
case it will be true that “some S are P” and that “some S are not P.” It
follows that at least one of a pair of subcontrary propositions must be true
and that both will be true in cases where P is partially predicated of S. So, for example, both
members of the subcontrary pair “some men have beards” and “some men do not
have beards” are true. They are both true because having a beard is a
contingent or variable male attribute. In contrast, only one member of the
subcontrary pair “some snakes are legless” and “some snakes are not legless” is
true. As all snakes are legless, the proposition “some snakes are not
legless” must be false.
Traditional logicians, inspired by Aristotle’s
wide-ranging comments, identified a series of “immediate inferences” as a way
of deriving new propositions through a routine rearrangement of terms. Subalternation
is an obvious example of immediate inference. From “All S are P” we can
immediately infer—that is, without argument—that “some S are P.” They
also recognized conversion, obversion, and contraposition as immediate
inferences.
In conversion,
one interchanges the S and P terms. If, for example, we know that “No S
is P,” we can immediately infer that “No P is S.” (Once we know that “no
circles are triangles,” we know right away that “no triangles are circles.”)
In obversion,
one negates the predicate term while replacing it with the predicate term of
opposite quality. If, for example, we know that “Some S are P,” we can
immediately infer the obverse, “Some S are not non-P.” (Once we know that
“some students are happy,” we know right away that “some students are not
unhappy.”)
Finally, in contraposition,
one negates both terms and reverses their order. If, for example, we know
that “All S are P,” we can infer the contrapositive “All non-P are
non-S.” (Once we know that “all voters are adults,” we know right away
that “all children are unable to vote.”) More specific rules,
restrictions, and details are readily available elsewhere.
6. Laws of Thought
During the 18th, 19th, and early 20th Century,
scholars who saw themselves as carrying on the Aristotelian and Medieval
tradition in logic, often pointed to the “laws of thought” as the basis of all
logic. One still encounters this approach in textbook accounts of
informal logic. The usual list of logical laws (or logical first
principles) includes three axioms: the law of identity, the law of
non-contradiction, and the law of excluded middle. (Some authors include
a law of sufficient reason, that every event or claim must have a sufficient
reason or explanation, and so forth.) It would be a gross simplification
to argue that these ideas derive exclusively from Aristotle or to suggest (as
some authors seem to imply) that he self-consciously presented a theory
uniquely derived from these three laws. The idea is rather that
Aristotle’s theory presupposes these principles and/or that he discusses or
alludes to them somewhere in his work. Traditional logicians did not
regard them as abstruse or esoteric doctrines but as manifestly obvious
principles that require assent for logical discourse to be possible.
The law of identity could be summarized as the
patently unremarkable but seemingly inescapable notion that things must be, of
course, identical with themselves. Expressed symbolically: “A is A,”
where A is an individual, a species, or a genus. Although Aristotle never
explicitly enunciates this law, he does observe, in the Metaphysics, that “the
fact that a thing is itself is [the only] answer to all such questions as why
the man is man, or the musician musical.” (VII.17.1041a16-18, Ross.) This
suggests that he does accept, unsurprisingly, the perfectly obvious idea that
things are themselves. If, however, identical things must possess
identical attributes, this opens the door to various logical maneuvers. One
can, for example, substitute equivalent terms for one another and, even more
portentously, one can arrive at some conception of analogy and induction.
Aristotle writes, “all water is said to be . . . the same as all
water . . . because of a certain likeness.” (Topics, I.7.103a19-20,
Pickard-Cambridge.) If water is water, then by the law of identity,
anything we discover to be water must possess the same water-properties.
Aristotle provides several formulations of the law of
non-contradiction, the idea that logically correct propositions cannot affirm
and deny the same thing:
“It is impossible for anyone to believe the same thing
to be and not be.” (Metaphysics,
IV.3.1005b23-24, Ross.)
“The same attribute cannot at the same time belong and
not belong to the same subject in the same respect.” (Ibid., IV.3.1005b19-20.)
“The most indisputable of all beliefs is that
contradictory statements are not at the same time true.” (Ibid.,
IV.6.1011b13-14.)
Symbolically, the law of non-contradiction is
sometimes represented as “not (A and not A).”
The law of
excluded middle can be summarized as the idea that every
proposition must be either true or false, not both and not neither. In Aristotle’s
words, “It is necessary for the affirmation or the negation to be true or
false.” (De Interpretatione,
9.18a28-29, Ackrill.) Symbolically, we can represent the law of excluded
middle as an exclusive disjunction: “A is true or A is false,” where only one
alternative holds. Because every proposition must be true or false, it
does not follow, of course, that we can know
if a particular proposition is true or false.
Despite perennial challenges to these so-called laws
(by intuitionists, dialetheists, and others), Aristotelians inevitably claim
that such counterarguments hinge on some unresolved ambiguity (equivocation),
on a conflation of what we know with what is actually the case, on a false or
static account of identity, or on some other failure to fully grasp the
implications of what one is saying.
7. Existential Assumptions
Before we move on to consider Aristotle’s account of
the syllogism, we need to clear up some widespread misconceptions and explain a
few things about Aristotle’s project as a whole. Criticisms of
Aristotle’s logic often assume that what Aristotle was trying to do coincides
with the basic project of modern logic. Begin with the usual criticism
brought against the traditional square of opposition. For reasons we will
not explore, modern logicians assume that universal claims about non-existent
objects (or empty sets) are true but that particular claims about them are
false. On this reading, the claim that “all fairy-god mothers are
beautiful” is true, whereas the claim that “some fairy-god mothers are
beautiful” is false. Clearly, this clashes with the traditional square of
opposition. By simple subalternation, the truth of the proposition “all
fairy-god mothers are beautiful” requires the truth of the proposition “some
fairy-god mothers are beautiful.” If the first claim is true, the second
claim must also be true. For this and similar reasons, some modern
logicians dismiss the traditional square as inadequate, claiming that Aristotle
made a mistake or overlooked relevant issues. Aristotle, however, is
involved in a specialized project. He elaborates an alternative logic,
specifically adapted to the problems he is trying to solve.
Aristotle devises a companion-logic for science.
He relegates fictions like fairy godmothers and mermaids and unicorns to the
realms of poetry and literature. In his mind, they exist outside the
ambit of science. This is why he leaves no room for such non-existent
entities in his logic. This is a thoughtful choice, not an inadvertent
omission. Technically, Aristotelian science is a search for definitions,
where a definition is “a phrase signifying a thing’s essence.” (Topics, I.5.102a37,
Pickard-Cambridge.) To possess an essence—is literally to possess a
“what-it-is-to-be” something (to ti ēn
einai). Because non-existent entities cannot be anything, they do not, in Aristotle’s
mind, possess an essence. They cannot be defined. Aristotle makes
this point explicitly in the Posterior
Analytics. He points out that a definition of a goat-stag, a
cross between a goat and a deer (the ancient equivalent of a unicorn), is
impossible. He writes, “no one knows the nature of what does not
exist—[we] can know the meaning of the phrase or name ‘goat-stag’ but not what
the essential nature of a goat-stag is.” (II.7.92b6-8, Mure.) Because we
cannot know what the essential nature of a goat-stag is—indeed, it has no
essential nature—we cannot provide a proper definition of a goat-stag. So
the study of goat-stags (or unicorns) is not open to scientific investigation.
Aristotle sets about designing a logic that is intended to display relations
between scientific propositions, where science is understood as a search for
essential definitions. This is why he leaves no place for fictional
entities like goat-stags (or unicorns). Hence, the assumed validity of a
logical maneuver like subalternation.
8. Form versus Content
However, this is not the only way Aristotle’s approach
parts ways with more modern assumptions. Some modern logicians might
define logic as that philosophical inquiry which considers the form not the
content of propositions. Aristotle’s logic is unapologetically
metaphysical. We cannot properly understand what Aristotle is about by
separating form from content. Suppose, for example, I was to claim that
(1) all birds have feathers and (2) that everyone in the Tremblay family wears
a red hat. These two claims possess the same very same propositional
form, A. We can represent the first claim as: “All S are P,” where
S=birds, and P=being feathered. And we can also represent the second
claim as “All S are P,” where S=members of the Tremblay family, and P=wearing a
red hat. Considered from an Aristotelian point of view, however, these
two “All S are P” propositions possess a very different logical status. Aristotle
would view the relationship between birds and feathers expressed in the first
proposition as a necessary link, for it is of the essence of birds to be
feathered. Something cannot be a bird and lack feathers. The link
between membership in the Tremblay family and the practice of wearing a red hat
described in the second proposition is, in sharp contrast, a contingent fact
about the world. A member of the Tremblay family who wore a green hat
would still be a member of the Tremblay family. The fact that the
Tremblays only wear red hats (because it is presently the fashion in Quebec) is
an accidental (or surface) feature of what a Tremblay is. So this second
relationship holds in a much weaker sense. In Aristotle’s mind, this has
important consequences not just for metaphysics, but for logic.
It is hard to capture in modern English the underlying
metaphysical force in Aristotle’s categorical statements. In the Prior Analytics Aristotle renders the
phrase “S is P” as “P belongs to S.” The sense of belonging here is crucial.
Aristotle wants a logic that tells us what belongs to what. But there are
different levels of belonging. My billfold belongs to me but this is a
very tenuous sort of belonging. The way my billfold belongs to me pales
in significance to, say, the way a bill belongs to a duck-billed
platypus. It is not simply that the bill is physically attached to the
platypus. Even if you were to cut off the bill of a platypus, this would
just create a deformed platypus; it would not change the sense of necessary
belonging that connects platypuses and bills. The deep nature of a
platypus requires—it necessitates—a
bill. In so much as logic is about discovering necessary relationships, it is not the
mere arrangement of terms and symbols but their substantive meaning that is at
issue.
As only one consequence of this “metaphysical
attitude,” consider Aristotle’s attitude towards inductive generalizations. Aristotle
would have no patience for the modern penchant for purely statistical
interpretations of inductive generalizations. It is not the number of
times something happens that matters. It is the deep nature of the thing
that counts. If the wicked boy (or girl) next door pulls three legs off a
spider, this is just happenstance. This five-legged spider does not (for
Aristotle) present a serious counterexample to the claim that “all spiders are
eight-legged.” The fact that someone can pull legs off a spider does not
change the fact that there is a necessary connection between spiders and having
eight legs. Aristotle is too keen a biologist not to recognize that there
are accidents and monstrosities in the world, but the existence of these
individual imperfections does not change the deep nature of things. Aristotle
recognizes then that some types of belonging are more substantial—that is, more
real—than others. But this has repercussions for the ways in which we
evaluate arguments. In Aristotle’s mind, the strength of the logical
connection that ties a conclusion to the premises in an argument depends,
decisively, on the metaphysical status of the claims we are making. Another
example may help. Suppose I were to argue, first: “Ostriches are
birds; all birds have feathers, therefore, ostriches have feathers.” Then,
second, “Hélène is the youngest daughter of the Tremblay family; all members of
the Tremblay family wear red hats; therefore, Hélène wears a red hat.” These
arguments possess the same form. (We will worry about formal details
later.) But, to Aristotle’s way of thinking, the first argument is,
logically, more rigorous than the second. Its conclusion follows from the
essential and therefore necessary features of birds. In the second
argument, the conclusion only follows from the contingent state of fashion in Quebec.
In Aristotelian logic, the strength of an argument depends, in some important
way, on metaphysical issues. We can’t simply say “All S are P; and so
forth” and be done with it. We have to know what “S” and “P” stand
for. This is very different than modern symbolic logic. Although
Aristotle does use letters to take the place of variable terms in a logical
relation, we should not be misled into thinking that the substantive content of
what is being discussed does not matter.
9. The Syllogism
We are now in a position to consider Aristotle’s
theory of the syllogism. Although one senses that Aristotle took great
pride in these accomplishments, we could complain that the persistent focus on
the mechanics of the valid syllogism has obscured his larger project. We
will only cover the most basic points here, largely ignoring hypothetical
syllogisms, modal syllogisms, extended syllogisms (sorites), inter alia. The syllogistic now
taught in undergraduate philosophy departments represents a later development
of Aristotle’s ideas, after they were reworked at the hands of Medieval and
modern logicians. We will begin with a brief account of the way
syllogisms are presented in modern logic and then move on to discussion of
Aristotle’s somewhat different account.
We can define a syllogism, in relation to its logical
form, as an argument made up of three categorical propositions, two premises
(which set out the evidence), and a conclusion (that follows logically from the
premises). In the standard account, the propositions are composed of
three terms, a subject term, a predicate term, and a middle term: the subject term is the
(grammatical) subject of the conclusion; the predicate term modifies the
subject in the conclusion, and the middle term links the subject and predicate
terms in the premises. The subject and predicate terms appear in
different premises; the middle term appears once in each premise. The
premise with the predicate term and the middle term is called the major premise; the premise with the subject
term and the middle term is called the minor
premise. Because syllogisms depend on the precise arrangement
of terms, syllogistic logic is sometimes referred to as term logic. Most readers of this
piece are already familiar with some version of a proverbial (non-Aristotelian)
example: “All men are mortal; (all) Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle are men;
therefore, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle are mortal.” If we symbolize the
three terms in this syllogism such that Middle
Term, M=man; Subject Term,
S=Socrates, Plato, Aristotle; Predicate
Term, P=mortal; we can represent the argument as: Major Premise: All M is P; Minor Premise: All S is M; Conclusion: So, All S is P. In
the Middle Ages, scholars came up with Latin names for valid syllogisms, using
vowels to represent the position of each categorical proposition. (Their
list is readily available elsewhere.) The precise arrangement of
propositions in this syllogism goes by the Latin moniker “Barbara” because the
syllogism is composed of three A propositions: hence, BArbArA: AAA.
A syllogism in Barbara is clearly valid where validity can be understood (in
modern terms) as the requirement that if the premises of the argument are true,
then the conclusion must be true. Modern textbook authors generally prove
the validity of syllogisms in two ways. First, they use a number of
different rules. For example: “when major and minor terms are universal
in the conclusion they must be universal in the premises”; “if one premise is negative, the conclusion
must be negative”; “the middle term in the premises must be distributed
(include every member of a class) at least once,” and so on. Second, they
use Venn diagrams, intersecting circles marked to indicate the extension (or
range) of different terms, to determine if the information contained in the
conclusion is also included in the premises.
Modern logicians, who still hold to traditional
conventions, classify syllogisms according to figure and mood. The four
figure classification derives from Aristotle; the mood classification, from
Medieval logicians. One determines the figure
of a syllogism by recording the positions the middle term takes in the two
premises. So, for Barbara above, the figure is MP-SM, generally referred
to as Figure 1. One determines the mood
of a syllogism by recording the precise arrangement of categorical
propositions. So, for Barbara, the mood is AAA. By tabulating
figures and moods, we can make an inventory of valid syllogisms. (Medieval
philosophers devised a mnemonic poem for such purposes that begins with the
line “Barbara, Celarent, Darii, Ferioque priorisis.” Details can be found
in many textbooks.) Although traditional classroom treatments prefer to
stick to this time-honoured approach, Fred Sommers and George Englebretsen have
devised a more up-to-date term logic that uses equations with “+” and “−”
operators and is more attuned to natural language reasoning than the usual
predicate logic. Turn then to a brief discussion of Aristotle’s own
account of the syllogism.
As already mentioned, we need to distinguish between
two kinds of necessity. Aristotle believes in metaphysical or natural
necessity. Birds must have feathers because that is their nature. So
the proposition “All birds have feathers” is necessarily true.” But
Aristotle identifies the syllogistic form with the logical necessity that obtains when two separate
propositions necessitate a third. He defines a sullogismos as “a discourse [logos] in which, certain things being stated, something
other than what is stated follows of necessity from them.” (Prior Analytics, I.1.24b18-20, Jenkinson.)
The emphasis here is on the sense of inevitable consequence that precipitates a
conclusion when certain forms of propositions are added together. Indeed,
the original Greek term for syllogism is more rigorously translated as
“deduction.” In the Prior Analytics,
Aristotle’s method is exploratory. He searches for pairs of propositions
that combine to produce a necessary conclusion. He begins by accepting
that a few syllogisms are self-evidently (or transparently) true. Barbara,
AAA-Fig.1, discussed above, is the best example of this kind of “perfect syllogism.” Another example
of a perfect syllogism is Celarent: EAE-Fig.1. On seeing the arrangement
of terms in such cases, one immediately understands that the conclusion follows
necessarily from the premises. In the case of imperfect syllogisms Aristotle relies on a method of proof
that translates them, step-by-step, into perfect syllogisms through a careful
rearrangement of terms. He does this directly, through conversion, or
indirectly, through the relationships of contradiction and contrariety outlined
in the square of opposition. To cite only one very simple example,
consider a brief passage in the Prior
Analytics (I.5.27a5ff) where Aristotle demonstrates that the
propositions “No P are M,” and “All S are M” can be combined to produce a
syllogism with the conclusion, “No S are P.” If “No P are M,” it must
follow that “No M are P” (conversion); but “No M are P” combined with the
second premise, “All S are M” proves that
“No S are P.” (This is to reduce the imperfect syllogism Cesare to the
perfect syllogism Celarent.) This conversion of an imperfect syllogism
into a perfect syllogism demonstrates that the original arrangement of terms is
a genuine deduction. In other cases, Aristotle proves that particular
arrangements of terms cannot yield proper syllogisms by showing that, in these
instances, true premises lead to obviously false or contradictory
conclusions. Alongside these proofs of logical necessity, Aristotle
derives general rules for syllogisms, classifies them according to figure, and
so on.
It is important to reiterate that Aristotelian
syllogisms are not (primarily) about hypothetical sets, imaginary classes, or
purely abstract mathematical entities. Aristotle believes there are
natural groups in the world—species and genera—made up of individual members
that share a similar nature, and hence similar properties. It is
this sharing of individual things in a similar nature that makes universal
statements possible. Once we have universal terms, we can make
over-arching statements that, when combined, lead inescapably to specific
results. In the most rigorous syllogistic, metaphysical necessity is
added to logical necessity to produce an unassailable inference. Seen in
this Aristotelian light, syllogisms can be construed as a vehicle for
identifying the deep, immutable natures that make things what they are.
Medieval
logicians summarized their understanding of the rationale underlying the
syllogism in the so-called dictum de omni et
nullo (the maxim of all and
none), the principle that whatever is affirmed or denied of a whole
must be affirmed or denied of a part (which they alleged derived from a reading
of Prior Analytics I.1.24b27-30).
Some contemporary authors have claimed that Aristotelian syllogistic is at
least compatible with a deflationary theory of truth, the modern idea that
truth-claims about propositions amount to little more than an assertion of the
statement itself. (To say that “S is P” is true, is just to assert “S is
P.”) Perhaps it would be better to say that one can trace the modern
preoccupation with validity in formal logic to the distinction between issues
of logical necessity and propositional truth implicit in Aristotle. In
Aristotle’s logic, arguments do not take the form: “this state of affairs is
true/false,” “this state of affairs is true/false,” therefore this state of
affairs is true/false.” We do not argue “All S is M is true” but merely,
“All S is M.” When it comes to determining validity—that is, when it
comes to determining whether we have discovered a true syllogism—the question
of the truth or falsity of propositions is pushed aside and attention is
focused on an evaluation of the logical connection between premises and
conclusion. Obviously, Aristotle recognizes that ascertaining the
material truth of premises is an important part of argument evaluation, but he
does not present a “truth-functional” logic. The concept of a “truth
value” does not play any explicit role in his formal analysis the way it does,
for example, with modern truth tables. Mostly, Aristotle wants to know
what we can confidently conclude from two presumably true premises; that is,
what kind of knowledge can be produced or demonstrated if two given premises
are true.
10. Inductive Syllogism
Understanding
what Aristotle means by inductive syllogism
is a matter of serious scholarly dispute. Although there is only
abbreviated textual evidence to go by, his account of inductive argument
can be supplemented by his ampler account of its rhetorical analogues, argument
from analogy and argument from example. What is clear is that Aristotle
thinks of induction (epagoge)
as a form of reasoning that begins in the sense perception of particulars and
ends in a understanding that can be expressed in a universal proposition (or
even a concept). We pick up mental momentum through a familiarity with
particular cases that allows us to arrive at a general understanding of an
entire species or genus. As we discuss below, there are indications that
Aristotle views induction, in the first instance, as a manifestation of
immediate understanding and not as an argument form. Nonetheless, in the Prior Analytics II.23 (and 24), he casts
inductive reasoning in syllogistic form, illustrating the “syllogism that
springs out of induction” (ho ex
epagoges sullogismos) by an
argument about the longevity of bileless animals.
Relying on old
biological ideas, Aristotle argues that we can move from observations about the
longevity of individual species of bileless animals (that is, animals with
clean-blood) to the universal conclusion that bilelessness is a cause of
longevity. His argument can be paraphrased in modern English: All men,
horses, mules, and so forth, are long-lived; all men, horses, mules, and so
forth, are bileless animals; therefore, all bileless animals are
long-lived. Although this argument seems, by modern standards, invalid,
Aristotle apparently claims that it is a valid deduction. (Remember that
the word “syllogism” means “deduction,” so an “inductive syllogism” is,
literally, an “inductive deduction.”) He uses a technical notion of “convertibility” to formally secure the
validity of the argument. According to this logical rule, terms that
cover the same range of cases (because they refer to the same nature) are
interchangeable (antistrepho).
They can be substituted for one another. Aristotle believes that because
the logical terms “men, horses, mules, etc” and “bileless animals” refer to the
same genus, they are convertible. If, however, we invert the terms in the
proposition “all men, horses, mules, and so forth, are bileless animals” to
“all bileless animals are men, horses, mules, and so forth,” we can then
rephrase the original argument: All men, horses, mules, and so forth, are
long-lived; all bileless animals are men, horses, mules, and so forth;
therefore, all bileless animals are long-lived. This revised induction
possesses an obviously valid form (Barbara, discussed above). Note that
Aristotle does not view this inversion of terms as a formal gimmick or trick;
he believes that it reflects something metaphysically true about shared natures
in the world. (One could argue that inductive syllogism operates by means
of the quantification of the predicate term as well as the subject term of a
categorical proposition, but we will not investigate that issue here.)
These passages
pose multiple problems of interpretation. We can only advance a general
overview of the most important disagreements here. We might identify four
different interpretations of Aristotle’s account of the inductive
syllogism. (1) The fact that Aristotle seems to view this as a
valid syllogism has led many commentators (such as Ross, McKirahan, Peters) to
assume that he is referring to what is known as “perfect induction,” a
generalization that is built up from a complete enumeration of particular
cases. The main problem here is that it seems to involve a physical
impossibility. No one could empirically inspect every bileless animal
(and/or species) to ascertain that the connection between bilelessness and
longevity obtains in every case. (2) Some commentators combine this first
explanation with the further suggestion that the bileless example is a rare
case and that Aristotle believes, in line with modern accounts, that most
inductions only produce probable belief. (Cf. Govier’s claim that there
is a “tradition going back to Aristotle, which maintains that there are .
. . only two broad types of argument: deductive arguments which are conclusive,
and inductive arguments, which are not.” (Problems in Argument Analysis, 52.)) One problem with
such claims is that they overlook the clear distinction that Aristotle makes
between rigorous inductions and rhetorical inductions (which we discuss
below). (3) Some commentators claim that Aristotle (and the
ancients generally) overlooked the inherent tenuousness of the inductive
reasoning. On this account, Empiricists such as Locke and Hume discovered
something seriously wrong about induction that escaped the notice of an ancient
author like Aristotle. Philosophers in the modern Anglo-American tradition largely favor this
interpretation. (Cf. Garrett’s and Barbanell’s insistence that “Hume was
the first to raise skeptical doubts about inductive reasoning, leaving a puzzle
as to why the concerns he highlighted had earlier been so completely
overlooked.” (“Induction,” 172.) Such allegations do not depend,
however, on any close reading of a wealth of relevant passages in the
Aristotelian corpus and in ancient philosophy generally. (4) Finally, a
minority contemporary view, growing in prominence, has argued that Aristotle
did not conceive of induction as an enumerative process but as a matter of
intelligent insight into natures. (Cf. McCaskey, Biondi, Rijk ,
Groarke.) On this account, Aristotle does not mean to suggest that
inductive syllogism depends on an empirical inspection of every member of a
group but on a universal act of understanding that operates through sense
perception. Aristotelian induction can best be compared to modern notions
of abduction or inference to the best explanation. This non-mathematical
account has historical precedents in neo-Platonism, Thomism, Idealism, and in
the textbook literature of traditionalist modern logicians that opposed the new
formal logic. This view has been criticized, however, as a form of mere
intuitionism dependent on an antiquated metaphysics.
The basic idea
that induction is valid will raise eyebrows, no doubt. It is important to
stave off some inevitable criticism before continuing. Modern accounts of
induction, deriving, in large part, from Hume and Locke, display a mania for
prediction. (Hence Hume’s question: how can we know that the future bread
we eat will nourish us based on past experience of eating bread?) But
this is not primarily how Aristotle views the problem. For Aristotle,
induction is about understanding natural
kinds. Once we comprehend the nature of something, we will,
of course, be able to make predictions about its future properties, but
understanding its nature is the key. In Aristotle’s mind, rigorous
induction is valid because it picks out those necessary and essential traits
that make something what it is. To use a very simple example,
understanding that all spiders have eight legs—that is, that all undamaged
spiders have eight legs—is a matter of knowing something deep about the
biological nature that constitutes a spider. Something that does not have
eight legs is not a spider. (Fruitful analogies might be drawn here to
the notion of “a posteriori
necessity” countenanced by contemporary logicians such as Hilary Putnam and
Saul Kripke or to the “revised” concept of a “natural kind” advanced by authors
such as Hilary Kornblith or Brian Ellis.)
It is commonly
said that Aristotle sees syllogisms as a device for explaining relationships
between groups. This is, in the main, true. Still, there has to be
some room for a consideration of individuals in logic if we hope to include
induction as an essential aspect of reasoning. As Aristotle explains,
induction begins in sense perception and sense perception only has individuals
as its object. Some commentators would limit inductive syllogism to a
movement from smaller groups (what Aristotle calls “primitive universals”) to
larger groups, but one can only induce a generalization about a smaller group
on the basis of a prior observation of individuals that compose that
group. A close reading reveals that Aristotle himself mentions syllogisms
dealing with individuals (about the moon, Topics,
78b4ff; about the wall, 78b13ff; about the eclipse, Posterior Analytics, 93a29ff,
and so on.) If we treat individuals as universal terms or as
representative of universal classes, this poses no problem for formal
analysis. Collecting observations about one individual or about
individuals who belong to a larger group can lead to an accurate
generalization.
11. Deduction versus Induction
We cannot fully
understand the nature or role of inductive syllogism in Aristotle without
situating it with respect to ordinary, “deductive” syllogism. Aristotle’s
distinction between deductive and inductive argument is not precisely
equivalent to the modern distinction. Contemporary authors differentiate
between deduction and induction in terms of validity. (A small group of
informal logicians called “Deductivists” dispute this account.) According
a well-worn formula, deductive arguments are valid; inductive arguments are
invalid. The premises in a deductive argument guarantee the truth of the
conclusion: if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. The
premises in an inductive argument provide some degree of support for the
conclusion, but it is possible to have true premises and a false conclusion.
Although some commentators attribute such views to Aristotle, this distinction
between strict logical necessity and merely probable or plausible reasoning
more easily maps onto the distinction Aristotle makes between scientific and
rhetorical reasoning (both of which we discuss below). Aristotle views
inductive syllogism as scientific (as opposed to rhetorical) induction and
therefore as a more rigorous form of inductive argument.
We can best
understand what this amounts to by a careful comparison of a deductive and an
inductive syllogism on the same topic. If we reconstruct, along
Aristotelian lines, a deduction on the longevity of bileless animals, the
argument would presumably run: All bileless animals are long-lived; all men,
horses, mules, and so forth, are bileless animals; therefore, all men, horses,
mules, and so forth, are long-lived. Defining the terms in this syllogism
as: Subject Term, S=men,
horses, mules, and so forth; Predicate Term,
P=long-lived animals; Middle Term,
M=bileless animals, we can represent this metaphysically correct inference
as: Major Premise: All M
are P. Minor Premise: All
S are M. Conclusion:
Therefore all S are P. (Barbara.) As we already have seen, the
corresponding induction runs: All men, horses, mules, and so forth, are long-lived;
all men, horses, mules, and so forth, are bileless animals; therefore, all
bileless animals are long-lived. Using the same definition of terms, we
are left with: Major Premise:
All S are P. Minor Premise:
All S are M (convertible to All M are S). Conclusion: Therefore, all M are P. (Converted to
Barbara.) The difference between these two inferences is the difference
between deductive and inductive argument in Aristotle.
Clearly,
Aristotelian and modern treatments of these issues diverge. As we have
already indicated, in the modern formalism, one automatically defines subject,
predicate, and middle terms of a syllogism according to their placement in the
argument. For Aristotle, the terms in a rigorous syllogism have a
metaphysical significance as well. In our correctly formulated
deductive-inductive pair, S represents individual species and/or the
individuals that make up those species (men, horses, mules, and so forth); M
represents the deep nature of these things (bilelessness), and P represents the
property that necessarily attaches to that nature (longevity). Here then
is the fundamental difference between Aristotelian deduction and induction in a
nutshell. In deduction, we prove that a property (P) belongs to
individual species (S) because it possesses a certain nature (M); in induction,
we prove that a property (P) belongs to a nature (M) because it belongs to
individual species (S). Expressed formally, deduction proves that the
subject term (S) is associated with a predicate term (P) by means of the middle
term (M); induction proves that the middle term (M) is associated with the
predicate term (P) by means of the subject term (S). (Cf. Prior Analytics, II.23.68b31-35.)
Aristotle does not claim that inductive syllogism is invalid but that the terms
in an induction have been rearranged. In deduction, the middle term joins
the two extremes (the subject and predicate terms); in induction, one extreme,
the subject term, acts as the middle term, joining the true middle term with the
other extreme. This is what Aristotle means when he maintains that in
induction one uses a subject term to argue to a middle term. Formally,
with respect to the arrangement of terms, the subject term becomes the “middle
term” in the argument.
Aristotle distinguishes
then between induction and deduction in three different ways. First,
induction moves from particulars to a
universal, whereas deduction moves from a universal to
particulars. The bileless induction moves from particular species to a
universal nature; the bileless deduction moves from a universal nature to
particular species. Second, induction moves from observation to language (that is, from sense perception
to propositions), whereas deduction moves from language to language (from
propositions to a new proposition). The bileless induction is really a
way of demonstrating how observations of bileless animals lead to
(propositional) knowledge about longevity; the bileless deduction demonstrates
how (propositional) knowledge of a universal nature leads (propositional)
knowledge about particular species. Third, induction identifies or explains a nature, whereas deduction
applies or demonstrates a nature. The bileless induction provides an
explanation of the nature of particular species: it is of the nature of
bileless organisms to possess a long life. The bileless deduction applies
that finding to particular species; once we know that it is of the nature of
bileless organisms to possess a long life, we can demonstrate or put on display
the property of longevity as it pertains to particular species.
One final point
needs clarification. The logical form of the inductive syllogism, after
the convertibility maneuver, is the same as the deductive syllogism. In
this sense, induction and deduction possess the same (final) logical
form. But, of course, in order to successfully perform an induction, one
has to know that convertibility is possible, and this requires an act of
intelligence which is able to discern the metaphysical realities between things
out in the world. We discuss this issue under non-discursive reasoning
below.
12. Science
Aristotle wants
to construct a logic that provides a working language for rigorous science as
he understands it. Whereas we have been talking of syllogisms as arguments,
Aristotelian science is about explanation.
Admittedly, informal logicians generally distinguish between explanation and
argument. An argument is intended to persuade about a debatable point; an
explanation is not intended to persuade so much as to promote
understanding. Aristotle views science as involving logical inferences
that move beyond what is disputable to a consideration of what is the
case. Still, the “explanatory” syllogisms used in science possess
precisely the same formal structures as “argumentative” syllogisms. So we
might consider them arguments in a wider sense. For his part, Aristotle
relegates eristic reason to the broad field of rhetoric. He views
science, perhaps naively, as a domain of established fact. The syllogisms
used in science are about establishing an explanation from specific cases
(induction) and then applying or illustrating this explanation to specific
cases (deduction).
The ancient Greek
term for science, “episteme,”
is not precisely equivalent to its modern counterpart. In Aristotle’s
worldview, science, as the most rigorous sort of discursive knowledge, is
opposed to mere opinion (doxa);
it is about what is universal and necessary as opposed to what is particular
and contingent, and it is theoretical as opposed to practical. Aristotle
believes that knowledge, understood as justified true belief, is most perfectly
expressed in a scientific demonstration (apodeixis),
also known as an apodeitic or scientific syllogism. He posits a number of specific
requirements for this most rigorous of all deductions. In order to
qualify as a scientific demonstration, a syllogism must possess premises that
are “true, primary, immediate, better known than, prior to, and causative of
the conclusion.” (Posterior Analytics,
I.2.71b20ff, Tredennick.) It must yield information about a natural kind
or a group of individual things. And it must produce universal knowledge
(episteme). Specialists
have disputed the meaning of these individual requirements, but the main
message is clear. Aristotle accepts, as a general rule, that a conclusion
in an argument cannot be more authoritative than the premises that led to that
conclusion. We cannot derive better (or more reliable) knowledge from
worse (or less reliable) knowledge. Given that a scientific demonstration
is the most rigorous form of knowledge possible, we must start with premises
that are utterly basic and as certain as possible, which are “immediately”
induced from observation, and which confirm to the necessary structure of the world
in a way that is authoritative and absolutely incontrovertible. This
requires a reliance on first principles which we discuss below.
In the best case
scenario, Aristotelian science is about finding definitions of
species that, according to a somewhat bald formula, identify the genus (the larger natural group) and the differentia (that unique feature that
sets the species apart from the larger group). As Aristotle’s focus on
definitions is a bit cramped and less than consistent (he himself spends a great
deal of time talking about necessary rather than essential properties), let us
broaden his approach to science to focus on ostensible definitions, where an
ostensible definition is either a rigorous definition or, more broadly, any
properly-formulated phrase that identifies the unique properties of
something. On this looser approach, which is more consistent with
Aristotle’s actual practice, to define an entity is to identify the nature, the
essential and necessary properties, that make it uniquely what it is.
Suffice it to say that Aristotle’s idealized account of what science entails
needs to be expanded to cover a wide range of activities and that fall under
what is now known as scientific practice. What follows is a general
sketch of his overall orientation. (We should point out that Aristotle
himself resorts to whatever informal methods seem appropriate when reporting on
his own biological investigations without too much concern for any fixed ideal
of formal correctness. He makes no attempt to cast his own scientific
conclusions in metaphysically-correct syllogisms. One could perhaps
insist that he uses enthymemes (syllogisms with unstated premises), but mostly,
he just seems to record what seems appropriate without any deliberate attempt
at correct formalization. Note that most of Aristotle’s scientific work
is “historia,” an earlier stage
of observing, fact-collecting, and opinion-reporting that proceeds the
principled theorizing of advanced science.)
For Aristotle,
even theology is a science insomuch as it deals with universal and necessary
principles. Still, in line with modern attitudes (and in opposition to
Plato), Aristotle views sense-perception as the proper route to scientific
knowledge. Our empirical experience of the world yields knowledge through
induction. Aristotle elaborates then an inductive-deductive model of
science. Through careful observation of particular species, the
scientist induces an ostensible definition to explain a nature and then
demonstrates the consequences of that nature for particular species.
Consider a specific case. In the Posterior
Analytics (II.16-17.98b32ff, 99a24ff), Aristotle mentions an
explanation about why deciduous plants lose their leaves in the winter.
The ancients apparently believed this happens because sap coagulates at the
base of the leaf (which is not entirely off the mark). We can use this
ancient example of a botanical explanation to illustrate how the business of
Aristotelian science is supposed to operate. Suppose we are a group of
ancient botanists who discover, through empirical inspection, why deciduous
plants such as vines and figs lose their leaves. Following Aristotle's
lead, we can cast our discovery in the form of the following inductive
syllogism: “Vine, fig, and so forth, are deciduous. Vine, fig, and
so forth, coagulate sap. Therefore, all sap-coagulators are
deciduous.” This induction produces the definition of “deciduous.”
(“Deciduous” is the definiendum;
sap-coagulation, the definiens;
the point being that everything
that is a sap-coagulator is deciduous, which might not be the case if we turned
it around and said “All deciduous plants are sap-coagulators.”) But once
we have a definition of “deciduous,” we can use it as the first premise in a
deduction to demonstrate something about say, the genus “broad-leaved
trees.” We can apply, in other words, what we have learned about
deciduous plants in general to the more specific genus of broad-leaved
trees. Our deduction will read: “All sap-coagulators are deciduous.
All broad-leaved trees are sap-coagulators. Therefore, all broad-leaved
trees are deciduous.” We can express all this symbolically. For the
induction, where S=vine, fig, and so forth, P=deciduous, M= being a
sap-coagulator, the argument is: “All S is P; all S is M (convertible to all M
is S); therefore, all M are P (converted to Barbara). For the deduction,
where S=broad-leafed trees, M=being a sap-coagulator, P=deciduous, the argument
can be represented: “All M are P; all S is M; therefore, all S is P”
(Barbara). This is then the basic logic of Aristotelian science.
A simple diagram
of how science operates follows (Figure 2).
Figure 2
The Inductive-Deductive Method of Aristotelian Science
Aristotle views
science as a search for causes (aitia).
In a well-known example about planets not twinkling because they are close to
the earth (Posterior Analytics,
I.13), he makes an important distinction between knowledge of the fact and knowledge of the reasoned fact. The
rigorous scientist aims at knowledge of the reasoned fact which explains why
something is the way it is. In our example, sap-coagulation is the cause
of deciduous; deciduous is not the cause of sap-coagulation. That is why
“sap-coagulation” is featured here as the middle term, because it is the cause
of the phenomenon being investigated. The deduction “All sap-coagulators
are deciduous; all broad-leaved trees are sap-coagulators; therefore, all
broad-leaved trees are deciduous” counts as knowledge of the reasoned fact
because it reveals the cause of broad-leafed deciduousness.
Aristotle makes a
further distinction between what is more knowable
relative to us and what is more knowable
by nature (or in itself). He remarks in the Physics, “The natural way of [inquiry] is
to start from the things which are more knowable and obvious to us and proceed
towards those which are clearer and more knowable by nature; for the same
things are not ‘knowable relatively to us’ and ‘knowable’ without
qualification.” (I.184a15, Hardie, Gaye.) In science we generally
move from the effect to the cause, from what we see and observe around us to
the hidden origins of things. The outward manifestation of the phenomenon
of “deciduousness” is more accessible to us because we can see the trees
shedding their leaves, but sap-coagulation as an explanatory principle is more
knowable in itself because it embodies the cause. To know about
sap-coagulation counts as an advance in knowledge; someone who knows this knows
more than someone who only knows that trees shed their leaves in the
fall. Aristotle believes that the job of science is to put on display
what best counts as knowledge, even if the resulting theory strays from our
immediate perceptions and first concerns.
Jan Lukasiewicz,
a modern-day pioneer in term logic, comments that “some queer philosophical
prejudices which cannot be explained rationally” made early commentators claim
that the major premise in a syllogism (the one with the middle and predicate
terms) must be first. (Aristotle’s
Syllogistic, 32.) But once we view the syllogism within the
larger context of Aristotelian logic, it becomes perfectly obvious why these
early commentators put the major premise first: because it constitutes the
(ostensible) definition; because it contains an explanation of the nature of
the thing upon which everything else depends. The major premise in a
scientific deduction is the most important part of the syllogism; it is
scientifically prior in that it reveals the cause that motivates the
phenomenon. So it makes sense to place it first. This was not an
irrational prejudice.
13. Non-Discursive Reasoning
The distinction
Aristotle draws between discursive knowledge (that is, knowledge through
argument) and non-discursive knowledge (that is, knowledge through nous) is akin to the medieval distinction
between ratio (argument) and intellectus (direct intellection).
In Aristotelian logic, non-discursive knowledge comes first and provides the
starting points upon which discursive or argumentative knowledge depends.
It is hard to know what to call the mental power that gives rise to this type
of knowledge in English. The traditional term “intuition” invites
misunderstanding. When Aristotle claims that there is an immediate sort
of knowledge that comes directly from the mind (nous) without discursive argument, he is not suggesting that
knowledge can be accessed through vague feelings or hunches. He is
referring to a capacity for intelligent appraisal that might be better
described as discernment, comprehension, or insight. Like his later
medieval followers, he views “intuition” as a species of reason; it is not
prior to reason or outside of reason, it is—in the highest degree—the activity
of reason itself. (Cf. Posterior
Analytics, II. 19; Nicomachean
Ethics, IV.6.)
For Aristotle,
science is only one manifestation of human intelligence. He includes, for
example, intuition, craft, philosophical wisdom, and moral decision-making
along with science in his account of the five intellectual virtues. (Nicomachean Ethics, VI.3-8.) When
it comes to knowledge-acquisition, however, intuition is primary. It
includes the most basic operations of intelligence, providing the ultimate
ground of understanding and inference upon which everything else depends.
Aristotle is a firm empiricist. He believes that knowledge begins in
perception, but he also believes that we need intuition to make sense of
perception. In the Posterior
Analytics (II.19.100a3-10), Aristotle posits a sequence of steps in
mental development: sense perception produces memory which (in combination with
intuition) produces human experience (empeiria),
which produces art and science. Through a widening movement of
understanding (really, a non-discursive form of induction), intuition
transforms observation and memory so as to produce knowledge (without
argument). This intuitive knowledge is even more reliable than
science. As Aristotle writes in key passages at the end of the Posterior Analytics, “no other kind of
thought except intuition is more accurate than scientific knowledge,” and
“nothing except intuition can be truer than scientific knowledge.” (100b8ff,
Mure, slightly emended.)
Aristotelian
intuition supplies the first principles
(archai) of human knowledge:
concepts, universal propositions, definitions, the laws of logic, the primary
principles of the specialized science, and even moral concepts such as the
various virtues. This is why, according to Aristotle, intuition must be
viewed as infallible. We cannot claim that the first principles of human
intelligence are dubious and then turn around and use those principles to make
authoritative claims about the possibility (or impossibility) of
knowledge. If we begin to doubt intuition, that is, human intelligence at
its most fundamental level of operation, we will have to doubt everything else
that is built upon this universal foundation: science, philosophy, knowledge,
logic, inference, and so forth. Aristotle never tries to prove first
principles. He acknowledges that when it comes to the origins of human
thought, there is a point when one must simply stop asking questions. As
he points out, any attempt at absolute proof would lead to an infinite
regress. In his own words: “It is impossible that there should be
demonstration of absolutely everything; there would be an infinite regress, so
that there would still be no demonstration.” (Metaphysics, 1006a6ff, Ross.) Aristotle does make
arguments, for example, that meaningful speech presupposes a logical axiom like
the principle of non-contradiction, but that is not, strictly speaking, a proof
of the principle.
Needless to say,
Aristotle’s reliance on intuition has provoked a good deal of scholarly
disagreement. Contemporary commentators such as Joseph Owens, G. L. Owen,
and Terrence Irwin have argued that Aristotelian first principles begin in
dialectic. On their influential account, we arrive at first principles
through a weaker form of argument that revolves around a consideration of “endoxa,” the proverbial opinions of the
many and/or the wise. Robin Smith (and others) severely criticize their
account. The idea that mere opinion could somehow give rise to rigorous
scientific knowledge conflicts with Aristotle’s settled view that less reliable
knowledge cannot provide sufficient logical support for the more reliable
knowledge. As we discuss below, endoxa
do provide a starting point for dialectical (and ethical) arguments in
Aristotle’s system. They are, in his mind, a potent intellectual
resource, a library of stored wisdom and right opinion. They may include
potent expressions of first principles already discovered by other thinkers and
previous generations. But as Aristotle makes clear at the end of the Posterior Analytics and elsewhere, the
recognition that something is a first principle depends directly on
intuition. As he reaffirms in the Nicomachean
Ethics, “it is intuitive reason that grasps the first
principles.” (VI.6.1141a7, Ross.)
If Irwin and his
colleagues seek to limit the role of intuition in Aristotle, authors such as
Lambertus Marie de Rijk and D. W. Hamlyn go to an opposite extreme, denying the
importance of the inductive syllogism and identifying induction (epagoge) exclusively with
intuition. De Rijk claims that Aristotelian induction is “a
pre-argumentation procedure consisting in . . . [a] disclosure [that] does not
take place by a formal, discursive inference, but is, as it were, jumped upon
by an intuitive act of knowledge.” (Semantics
and Ontology, I.2.53, 141-2.) Although
this position seems extreme, it seems indisputable that inductive syllogism
depends on intuition, for without intuition (understood as intelligent
discernment), one could not recognize the convertibility of subject and middle
terms (discussed above). Aristotle also points out that one needs
intuition to recognize the (ostensible) definitions so crucial to the practice
of Aristotelian science. We must be able to discern the difference between accidental and necessary or
essential properties before coming up with a definition. This can only
come about through some kind of direct (non-discursive) discernment.
Aristotle proposes a method for discovering definitions called division—we are to divide things into
smaller and smaller sub-groups—but this method depends wholly on nous. (Cf. Posterior Analytics, II.13.) Some
modern Empiricist commentators, embarrassed by such mystical-sounding
doctrines, warn that this emphasis on non-discursive reasoning collapses into
pure rationalism (or Platonism), but this is a caricature. What Aristotle
means by rational “intuition” is not a matter of pure, disembodied
thought. One does not arrive at first principles by closing one’s eyes
and retreating from the world (as with Cartesian introspection). For
Aristotle, first principles arise through a vigorous interaction of the
empirical with the rational; a combination of rationality and sense experience
produces the first seeds of human understanding.
Note that
Aristotle believes that there are first principles (koinai archai) that are common to all fields of inquiry,
such as the principle of non-contradiction or the law of excluded middle, and
that each specialized science has its own first principles. We may
recover these first principles second-hand by a (dialectical) review of
authorities. Or, we can derive them first hand by analysis, by dividing
the subject matter we are concerned with into its constituent parts. At
the beginning of the Physics,
Aristotle explains, “What is to us plain and obvious at first is rather
confused masses, the elements and principles of which become known to us later
by analysis. Thus we must advance from generalities to particulars; for it is a
whole that is best known to sense-perception, and a generality is a kind of
whole, comprehending many things within it, like parts. . . .
Similarly a child begins by calling all men ‘father,’ and all women ‘mother,’
but later on distinguishes each of them.” (I.1.184a22-184b14, Hardie,
Gaye.) Just as children learn to distinguish their parents from other
human beings, those who successfully study a science learn to distinguish the
different natural kinds that make up the whole of a scientific
phenomenon. This precedes the work of induction and deduction already
discussed. Once we have the parts (or the aspects), we can reason about them
scientifically.
14. Rhetoric
Argumentation
theorists (less aptly characterized as informal logicians) have critiqued the
ascendancy of formal logic, complaining that the contemporary penchant for
symbolic logic leaves one with an abstract mathematics of empty signs that
cannot be applied in any useful way to larger issues. Proponents of formal
logic counter that their specialized formalism allows for a degree of precision
otherwise not available and that any focus on the substantive meaning or truth
of propositions is a distraction from logical issues per se. We cannot readily fit
Aristotle into one camp or the other. Although he does provide a formal
analysis of the syllogism, he intends logic primarily as a means of acquiring
true statements about the world. He also engages in an enthusiastic
investigation of less rigorous forms of reasoning included in the study of
dialectic and rhetoric.
Understanding
precisely what Aristotle means by the term “dialectics”
(dialektike) is no easy
task. He seems to view it as the technical study of argument in general
or perhaps as a more specialized investigation into argumentative
dialogue. He intends his rhetoric (rhetorike),
which he describes as the counterpart to dialectic, as an expansive study of
the art of persuasion, particularly as it is directed towards a non-academic
public. Suffice it to say, for our purposes, that Aristotle reserves a
place in his logic for a general examination of all arguments, for scientific
reasoning, for rhetoric, for debating techniques of various sorts, for
jurisprudential pleading, for cross-examination, for moral reasoning, for
analysis, and for non-discursive intuition.
Aristotle
distinguishes between what I will call, for convenience, rigorous logic and
persuasive logic. Rigorous logic
aims at epistēmē, true belief
about what is eternal, necessary, universal, and unchanging. (Aristotle
sometimes qualifies this to include “for the most part” scientific
knowledge.) Persuasive logic
aims at acceptable, probable, or convincing belief (what we might call
“opinion” instead of knowledge.) It deals with approximate truth, with endoxa (popular or proverbial opinions),
with reasoning that is acceptable to a particular audience, or with claims
about accidental properties and contingent events. Persuasive syllogisms
have the same form as rigorous syllogisms but are understood as establishing
their conclusions in a weaker manner. As we have already seen, rigorous
logic produces deductive and inductive syllogisms; Aristotle indicates that
persuasive logic produces, in a parallel manner, enthymemes, analogies, and
examples. He defines an enthymeme
as a deduction “concerned with things which may, generally speaking, be other
than they are,” with matters that are “for the most part only generally
true,” or with “probabilities and signs” (Rhetoric, I.2.1357a, Roberts). He
also mentions that the term “enthymeme” may refer to arguments with missing
premises. (Rhetoric,
1.2.1357a16-22.) When it comes to induction, Aristotle’s presentation is
more complicated, but we can reconstruct what he means in a more
straightforward manner.
The persuasive
counterpart to the inductive syllogism is the analogy and the example,
but the example is really a composite argument formed from first, an analogy
and second, an enthymeme. Some initial confusion is to be expected as
Aristotle’s understanding of analogies differs somewhat from contemporary
accounts. In contemporary treatments, analogies depend on a direct
object(s)-to-object(s) comparison. Aristotelian analogy, on the other
hand, involves reasoning up to a general principle. We are to conclude
(1) that because individual things of a certain nature X have property z,
everything that possesses nature X has property z. But once we know that
every X possesses property z, we can make a deduction (2) that some new example
of nature X will also have property z. Aristotle calls (1), the inductive
movement up to the generalization, an analogy (literally, an argument from
likeness=ton homoion); he calls
(2), the deductive movement down to a new case, an enthymeme; and he considers
(1) + (2), the combination of the analogy and the enthymeme together, an
example (paradeigma). He
presents the following argument from example in the Rhetoric (I.2.1357b31-1358a1). Suppose we wish to
argue that Dionysus, the ruler, is asking for a bodyguard in order to set
himself up as despot. We can establish this by a two-step process.
First, we can draw a damning analogy between previous cases where rulers asked
for a bodyguard and induce a general rule about such practices. We can
insist that Peisistratus, Theagenes, and other known tyrants, were scheming to
make themselves despots, that Peisistratus, Theagenes, and other known tyrants
also asked for a bodyguard, and that therefore, everyone who asks for a
bodyguard is scheming to make themselves dictators. But once we have
established this general rule, we can move on to the second step in our
argument, using this conclusion as a premise in an enthymeme. We can
argue that all people asking for a bodyguard are scheming to make themselves
despots, that Dionysius is someone asking for a bodyguard, and that therefore,
Dionysius must be scheming to make himself despot. This is not, in
Aristotle’s mind, rigorous reasoning. Nonetheless, we can, in this way, induce probable conclusions and then use
them to deduce probable
consequences. Although these arguments are intended to be persuasive or
plausible rather than scientific, but the reasoning strategy mimics the
inductive-deductive movement of science (without compelling, of course, the
same degree of belief).
We should point
out that Aristotle does not restrict himself to a consideration of purely
formal issues in his discussion of rhetoric. He famously distinguishes,
for example, between three means of persuasion: ethos, pathos,
and logos. As we read, at
the beginning of his Rhetoric:
“Of the modes of persuasion furnished by the spoken word there are three kinds.
. . . [Firstly,] persuasion is achieved by the speaker's personal character
when the speech is so spoken as to make us think him credible. . . . Secondly,
persuasion may come through the hearers, when the speech stirs their emotions.
. . . Thirdly, persuasion is effected through the speech itself when we have
proved [the point] by means of the persuasive arguments suitable to the case in
question.” (Rhetoric,
I.2.1356a2-21, Roberts.) Aristotle concludes that effective arguers must
(1) understand morality and be able to convince an audience that they
themselves are good, trustworthy people worth listening to (ethos); (2) know the general causes of
emotion and be able to elicit them from specific audience (pathos); and (3) be able to use logical
techniques to make convincing (not necessarily sound) arguments (logos). Aristotle broaches many
other issues we cannot enter into here. He acknowledges that the goal of
rhetoric is persuasion, not truth. Such techniques may be bent to immoral
or dishonest ends. Nonetheless, he insists that it is in the public
interest to provide a comprehensive and systematic survey of the field.
We might mention
two other logical devices that have a place in Aristotle’s work: the topos and the aporia. Unfortunately, Aristotle never explicitly
explains what a topos is.
The English word “topic” does not do justice to the original notion, for
although Aristotelian topoi may
be organized around subject matter, they focus more precisely on recommended
strategies for successful arguing. (The technical term derives from a
Greek word referring to a physical location. Some scholars suggest a link
to ancient mnemonic techniques that superimposed lists on familiar physical
locations as a memory aid.) In relevant discussions (in the Topics and the Rhetoric)
Aristotle offers helpful advice about finding (or remembering) suitable
premises, about verbally out-manoeuvring an opponent, about finding forceful
analogies, and so on. Examples of specific topoi would include discussions about how to argue which is
the better of two alternatives, how to substitute terms effectively, how to
address issues about genus and property, how to argue about cause and effect,
how to conceive of sameness and difference, and so on. Some commentators
suggest that different topoi
may have been used in a classroom situation in conjunction with student
exercises and standardized texts, or with written lists of endoxa, or even with ready-made arguments
that students were expected to memorize.
An aporia is a
common device in Greek philosophy. The Greek word aporia (plural, aporiai) refers to a physical location
blocked off by obstacles where there is no way out; by extension, it means, in
philosophy, a mental perplexity, an impasse, a paradox or puzzle that stoutly
resists solution. Aristotle famously suggests that philosophers begin
with aporiai and complete their
task by resolving the apparent paradoxes. An attentive reader will
uncover many aporiai in
Aristotle who begins many of his treatises with a diaporia, a survey of the puzzles that occupied previous
thinkers. Note that aporiai cannot
be solved through some mechanical rearrangement of symbolic terms.
Solving puzzles requires intelligence and discernment; it requires some
creative insight into what is at stake.
15. Fallacies
In a short work
entitled Sophistical Refutations,
Aristotle introduces a theory of logical fallacies that has been remarkably
influential. His treatment is abbreviated and somewhat obscure, and there
is inevitably scholarly disagreement about precise exegesis. Aristotle
thinks of fallacies as
instances of specious reasoning;
they are not merely errors but hidden
errors. A fallacy is an incorrect reasoning strategy that gives the
illusion of being sound or somehow conceals the underlying problem.
Aristotle divides fallacies into two broad categories: those which depend on
language (sometimes called verbal fallacies) and those that are independent of
language (sometimes called material fallacies). There is some scholarly
disagreement about particular fallacies, but traditional English names and
familiar descriptions follow. Linguistic fallacies include: homonymy
(verbal equivocation), ambiguity (amphiboly or grammatical equivocation),
composition (confusing parts with a whole), division (confusing a whole with
parts), accent (equivocation that arises out of mispronunciation or misplaced
emphasis) and figure of speech (ambiguity resulting from the form of an
expression). Independent fallacies include accident (overlooking
exceptions), converse accident (hasty generalization or improper
qualification), irrelevant conclusion, affirming the consequent (assuming an
effect guarantees the presence of one possible cause), begging the question
(assuming the point), false cause, and complex question (disguising two or more
questions as one). Logicians, influenced by scholastic logic, often gave
these characteristic mistakes Latin names: compositio
for composition, divisio for
division, secundum quid et simpliciter
for converse accident, ignoranti enlenchi
for nonrelevant conclusion, and petitio
principii for begging the question.
Consider three
brief examples of fallacies from Aristotle’s original text. Aristotle
formulates the following amphiboly (which admittedly sounds awkward in
English): “I wish that you the enemy may capture.” (Sophistical Refutations, 4.166a7-8, Pickard-Cambridge.)
Clearly, the grammatical structure of the statement leaves it ambiguous as to
whether the speaker is hoping that the enemy or “you” be captured. In
discussing complex question, he supplies the following perplexing example:
“Ought one to obey the wise or one’s father?” (Ibid., 12.173a21.)
Obviously, from a Greek perspective, one ought to obey both. The problem
is that the question has been worded in such a way that anyone who answers will
be forced to reject one moral duty in order to embrace the other. In
fact, there are two separate questions here—Should one obey the wise?
Should one obey one’s father?—that have been illegitimately combined to produce
a single question with a single answer. Finally, Aristotle provides the
following time-honoured example of affirming the consequent: “Since after the
rain the ground is wet, we suppose that if the ground is wet, it has been
raining; whereas that does not necessarily follow” (Ibid.,
5.167b5-8.) Aristotle’s point is that assuming that the same effect never
has more than one cause misconstrues the true nature of the world. The
same effect may have several causes. Many of Aristotle’s examples have to
do with verbal tricks which are entirely unconvincing—for example, the person
who commits the fallacy of division by arguing that the number “5” is both even
and odd because it can be divided into an even and an odd number: “2” and
“3.” (Ibid., 4.166a32-33.) But the interest here is theoretical:
figuring out where an obviously-incorrect argument or proposition went
wrong. We should note that much of this text, which deals with natural
language argumentation, does not presuppose the syllogistic form.
Aristotle does spend a good bit of time considering how fallacies are related
to one another. Fallacy theory, it is worth
adding, is a thriving area of research in contemporary argumentation
theory. Some of these issues are hotly debated.
16. Moral Reasoning
In the modern
world, many philosophers have argued that morality is a matter of feelings, not
reason. Although Aristotle recognizes the connative (or emotional) side
of morality, he takes a decidedly different tack. As a virtue
ethicist, he does not focus on moral law but views morality through
the lens of character. An ethical person develops a capacity for habitual
decision-making that aims at good, reliable traits such as honesty, generosity,
high-mindedness, and courage. To modern ears, this may not sound like
reason-at-work, but Aristotle argues that only human beings—that is, rational animals—are able to tell the
difference between right and wrong. He widens his account of rationality
to include a notion of practical wisdom
(phronesis), which he defines
as “a true and reasoned state of capacity to act with regard to the things that
are good or bad for man.” (Nicomachean
Ethics, VI.5.1140b4-5, Ross, Urmson). The operation of
practical wisdom, which is more about doing than thinking, displays an
inductive-deductive pattern similar to science as represented in Figure
3. It depends crucially on intuition or nous. One induces the idea of specific virtues
(largely, through an exercise of non-discursive reason) and then deduces how to
apply these ideas to particular circumstances. (Some scholars make a
strict distinction between “virtue” (areté)
understood as the mental capacity which induces moral ideas and “phronesis” understood as the mental
capacity which applies these ideas, but the basic structure of moral thinking
remains the same however strictly or loosely we define these two terms.)
Figure 3
The Inductive-Deductive Method of Aristotelian Ethics
We can
distinguish then between moral induction and moral deduction. In moral
induction, we induce an idea of courage, honesty, loyalty, and so on. We
do this over time, beginning in our childhood, through habit and
upbringing. Aristotle writes that the successful moral agent “must be
born with an eye, as it were, by which to judge rightly and choose what is
truly good.” (Ibid., VI.7.1114b6ff.) Once this intuitive capacity
for moral discernment has been sufficiently developed—once the moral eye is
able to see the difference
between right and wrong,—we can apply moral norms to the concrete circumstances
of our own lives. In moral deduction, we go on to apply the idea of a
specific virtue to a particular situation. We do not do this by
formulating moral arguments inside our heads, but by making reasonable
decisions, by doing what is morally required given the circumstances.
Aristotle refers, in this connection, to the practical
syllogism which results “in a conclusion which is an action.” (Movement of Animals, 701a10ff,
Farquharson.) Consider a (somewhat simplified) example.
Suppose I induce the idea of promise-keeping as a virtue and then apply it to
question of whether I should pay back the money I borrowed from my
brother. The corresponding theoretical
syllogism would be: Promise-keeping is good; giving back the
money I owe my brother is an instance of promise-keeping; so giving the back
the money I owe my brother is good.” In the corresponding practical syllogism, I do not conclude
with a statement: “this act is good.” I go out and pay back the
money I owe my brother. The physical exchange of money counts as the
conclusion. In Aristotle’s moral system, general moral principles play
the role of an ostensible definition in science. One induces a general principle and deduces a corresponding action.
Aristotle does believe that moral reasoning is a less rigorous form of
reasoning than science, but chiefly because scientific demonstrations deal with
universals whereas the practical syllogism ends a single act that must be
fitted to contingent circumstances. There is never any suggestion that
morality is somehow arbitrary or subjective. One could set out the moral
reasoning process using the moral equivalent of an inductive syllogism and a
scientific demonstration.
Although
Aristotle provides a logical blueprint for the kind of reasoning that is going
on in ethical decision-making, he obviously does not view moral decision-making
as any kind of mechanical or algorithmic procedure. Moral induction and
deduction represent, in simplified form,
what is going on. Throughout his ethics, Aristotle emphasizes the
importance of context. The practice of morality depends then on a faculty
of keen discernment that notices, distinguishes, analyzes, appreciates,
generalizes, evaluates, and ultimately decides. In the Nicomachean Ethics, he includes practical
wisdom in his list of five intellectual virtues. (Scholarly commentators
variously explicate the relationship between the moral and the intellectual
virtues.) Aristotle also discusses minor moral virtues such as good
deliberation (eubulia),
theoretical moral understanding (sunesis),
and experienced moral judgement (gnome).
And he equates moral failure with chronic ignorance or, in the case of weakness
of will (akrasia), with
intermittent ignorance.
17. References and Further Reading
a. Primary Sources
- Complete Works of Aristotle. Edited by Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984.
- The standard scholarly collection of translations.
- Aristotle in 23 Volumes. Cambridge, M.A.: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd., 1944 and 1960.
- A scholarly, bilingual edition.
b. Secondary Sources
This list is
intended as a window on a diversity of approaches and problems.
- Barnes, Jonathan, (Aristotle) Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York : Oxford University Press, 1994.
- Biondi, Paolo. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics II.19. Quebec, Q.C.: Les Presses de l’Universite Laval, 2004.
- Ebbesen, Sten, Commentators and Commentaries on Aristotle’s Sophistici Elenchi, Vol. 1: The Greek Tradition. Leiden: Brill, 1981.
- Engberg-Pedersen, Troels. “More on Aristotelian Epagoge.” Phronesis, 24 (1979): 301-319.
- Englebretsen, George. Three Logicians: Aristotle, Leibnitz, and Sommers and the Syllogistic. Assen, Netherlands: Van Gorcum, 1981.
- See also Sommers, below.
- Garrett, Dan, and Edward Barbanell. Encyclopedia of Empiricism. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1997.
- Govier, Trudy. Problems in Argument Analysis and Evaluation. Providence, R.I.: Floris, 1987.
- Groarke, Louis. “A Deductive Account of Induction,” Science et Esprit, 52 (December 2000), 353-369.
- Groarke, Louis. An Aristotelian Account of Induction: Creating Something From Nothing. Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2009.
- Hamlyn, D. W. Aristotle’s De Anima Books II and III. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974.
- Hamlyn, D. W. “Aristotelian Epagoge.” Phronesis 21 (1976): 167-184.
- Irwin, Terence. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988.
- Keyt, David. “Deductive Logic,” in A Companion to Aristotle, George Anaganostopoulos, London: Blackwell, 2009, pp. 31-50.
- Łukasiewicz, Jan. Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. Oxford University Press, 1957.
- McCaskey, John, “Freeing Aristotelian Epagôgê from Prior Analytics II 23,” Apeiron, 40:4 (December, 2007), pp. 345–74.
- McKirahan, Richard Jr. Principles and Proofs: Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Species. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992.
- Parry, William, and Edward Hacker. Aristotelian Logic. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1991.
- Peters, F. E., Greek Philosophical Terms: A Historical Lexicon. New York: NYU Press, 1967.
- Rijk, Lambertus Marie de. Aristotle: Semantics and Ontology. Boston, M.A.: Brill, 2002.
- Smith, Robin. “Aristotle on the Uses of Dialectic,” Synthese , Vol. 96, No. 3, 1993, 335-358.
- Smith, Robin. Aristotle, Prior Analytics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1989.
- Smith, Robin. “Aristotle’s Logic,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. E, Zalta. ed. Stanford, CA., 2000, 2007.
- An excellent introduction to Aristotle’s logic (with a different focus).
- Smith, Robin. “Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstration,” in A Companion to Aristotle, 52-65.
- Sommers, Fred, and George Englebretsen, An Invitation to Formal Reasoning: The Logic of Terms. Aldershot UK: Ashgate, 2000.
Author Information
Aristotle: Metaphysics
When Aristotle articulated the
central question of the group of writings we know as his Metaphysics, he said it was a question
that would never cease to raise itself. He was right. He also regarded his own
contributions to the handling of that question as belonging to the final phase
of responding to it. I think he was right about that too. The Metaphysics is one of the most helpful
books there is for contending with a question the asking of which is one of the
things that makes us human. In our time that question is for the most part
hidden behind a wall of sophistry, and the book that could lead us to
rediscover it is even more thoroughly hidden behind a maze of
misunderstandings.
Paul Shorey, a
scholar whose not-too-bad translation of the Republic is the Hamilton edition of the Collected Works of Plato, has called
the Metaphysics "a
hopeless muddle" not to be made sense of by any "ingenuity of
conjecture." I think it is safe to say that more people have learned
important things from Aristotle than from Professor Shorey, but what conclusion
other than his can one come to about a work that has two books numbered one,
that descends from the sublime description of the life of the divine intellect
in its twelfth book to end with two books full of endless quarreling over minor
details of the Platonic doctrine of forms, a doctrine Aristotle had already
decisively refuted in early parts of the book, those parts, that is, in which
he is not defending it? The book was certainly not written as one whole; it was
compiled, and once one has granted that, must not one admit that it was
compiled badly, crystallizing as it does an incoherent ambivalence toward the
teachings of Plato? After three centuries in which no one has much interest in
it at all, the Metaphysics
becomes interesting to nineteenth century scholars just as a historical puzzle:
how could such a mess have been put together?
I have learned
the most from reading the Metaphysics
on those occasions when I have adopted the working hypothesis that it was
compiled by someone who understood Aristotle better than I or the scholars do,
and that that someone (why not call him Aristotle?) thought that the parts made
an intelligible whole, best understood when read in that order. My main
business here will be to give you some sense of how the Metaphysics looks in its wholeness, but
the picture I will sketch depends on several hypotheses independent of the main
one. One cannot begin to read the Metaphysics
without two pieces of equipment: one is a set of decisions about how to
translate Aristotle's central words. No translator of Aristotle known to me is
of any help here; they will all befuddle you, more so in the Metaphysics even than in Aristotle's
other works. The other piece of equipment, and equally indispensable I think,
is some perspective on the relation of the Metaphysics to the Platonic dialogues. In this matter the
scholars, even the best of them, have shown no imagination at all. In the
dialogues, in their view, Plato sets forth a "theory" by putting it
into the mouth of Socrates. There is some room for interpretation, but on the
whole we are all supposed to know that theory. Aristotle must accept that
theory or reject it. If he appears to do both it is because passages written by
some Platonist have been inserted into his text, or because things he wrote
when he was young and a Platonist were lumped together with other things on
similar subjects which he wrote when he was older and his thoughts were
different and his own.
Table of Contents
- Aristotle and Plato
- Translating Aristotle
- The Meaning of Ousia (Being) in Plato
- Ousia in Aristotle
- The Doctrine of Categories
- The Central Question of the Metaphysics
- The World as Cosmos
- Forms, Wholeness, and Thinghood
- The Being of Sensible Things
- Matter and Form in Aristotle
- References and Further Reading
1. Aristotle and Plato
The Plato we are
supposed to know from his dialogues is one who posited that, for every name we
give to bodies in the world there is a bodiless being in another world, one
while they are many, static while they are changing, perfect while they are
altogether distasteful. Not surprisingly, those for whom this is Plato find his
doctrine absurd, and welcome an Aristotle whom they find saying that being in
its highest form is found in an individual man or horse, that mathematical
things are abstractions from sensible bodies, and that, if there is an ideal
man apart from men, in virtue of whom they are all called men, then there must
be yet a third kind of man, in virtue of whom the form and the men can have the
same name, and yet a fourth, and so on. You can't stop adding new ideal men
until you are willing to grant that it was absurd to add the first one, or
anything at all beyond just plain men. This is hard-headed, tough-minded
Aristotle, not to be intimidated by fancy, mystical talk, living in the world
we live in and knowing it is the only world there is. This Aristotle,
unfortunately, is a fiction, a projection of our unphilosophic selves. He lives
only in a handful of sentences ripped out of their contexts. The true Aristotle
indeed takes at face value the world as we find it and all our ordinary
opinions about it--takes them, examines them, and finds them wanting. It is the
world as we find it which continually, for Aristotle, shows that our ordinary,
materialist prejudices are mistaken, and the abandonment of those prejudices
shows in turn that the world as we found it was not a possible world, that the
world as we must reflect upon it is a much richer world, mysterious and
exciting.
Those of you for
whom reading the Platonic dialogues was a battle you won by losing, an
eye-opening experience from which, if there is no going forward, there is
certainly no turning back, should get to know this Aristotle. But you will find
standing in your way all those passages in which Aristotle seems to be
discussing the dialogues and does so in a shallow way. Each dialogue has a
surface in which Socrates speaks in riddles, articulates half-truths which
invite qualification and correction, argues from answers given by others as
though he shared their opinions, and pretends to be at a loss about everything.
Plato never straightens things out for his readers, any more than Socrates does
for his hearers. To do so would be to soothe us, to lull us to sleep as soon as
we've begun to be distressed by what it feels like to be awake. Platonic
writing, like Socratic talk, is designed to awaken and guide philosophic
thinking, by presenting, defending, and criticizing plausible responses to
important questions. The Platonic-Socratic words have only done their work when
we have gone beyond them, but they remain in the dialogues as a collection of
just what they were intended to be -- unsatisfactory assertions. Hippocrates
Apostle finds 81 places in the Metaphysics
where Aristotle disagrees with Plato. It is not surprising that Aristotle
himself uses Plato's name in almost none of those places. Aristotle is
addressing an audience of students who have read the dialogues and is
continuing the work of the dialogues. Many, perhaps most, of Aristotle's
students would, like scholars today, find theories and answers in Plato's
dialogues. Aristotle would not be earning his keep as a teacher of philosophy
if he did not force his students beyond that position. Aristotle constantly
refers to the dialogues because they are the best and most comprehensive texts
he and his students share. Aristotle disagrees with Plato about some things,
but less extensively and less deeply than he disagrees with every other author
that he names. The Metaphysics
inevitably looks like an attack on Plato just because Plato's books are so much
better than anything left by Thales, Empedocles or anyone else.
My first
assumption, then, was that the Metaphysics
is one book with one complex argument, and my second is that, in cohering
within itself, the Metaphysics
may cohere with the Platonic dialogues. I assume that discussions in the
dialogues may be taken as giving flesh to Aristotle's formulations, while they
in turn may be taken as giving shape to those discussions. One need only try a
very little of this to find a great deal beginning to fall into place. For
example, listen to Aristotle in Book I, Chapter 9 of the Metaphysics: "the Forms ...are not
the causes of motion or of any other change ...And they do not in any way help
either towards the knowledge of the other things..or towards their existence
...Moreover, all other things do not come to be from the Forms in any of the
usual senses of 'from.' And to say that the Forms are patterns and that the
other things participate in them is to use empty words and poetic
metaphors." A devastating attack on Plato, is it not? Or is it? Aristotle
says that positing the Forms explains no single thing that one wants to know.
But doesn't Socrates say in the Phaedo
that to call beauty itself the cause of beauty in beautiful things is a
"safe but stupid answer"--that one must begin with it but must also
move beyond it? Again, everyone knows that the Platonic Socrates claimed that
the forms were separate from the things in the sensible world, off by
themselves, while Aristotle insisted that the forms were in the things. Recall
the Phaedo passage just
referred to. Does not Socrates say that the cause of heat in a hot thing is not
heat itself but fire? Where, then, is the form for Socrates? Aristotle taught
that the causes of characteristics of things were to be looked for not in a
separate world of forms but in the primary instances of those characteristics
right here in the world. This doctrine may seem to be a rejection of Plato's
chief postulate, but listen to Aristotle himself explain it in Book II, Chapter
1 of the Metaphysics:
"of things to which the same predicate belongs, the one to which it
belongs in the highest degree is that in virtue of which it belongs also to the
others. For example, fire is the hottest of whatever is truly called 'hot', for
fire is cause of hotness in the others." Do you hear an echo? Again,
Aristotle teaches that form is to be understood as always at work, never static
as is the Platonic form, or is it? Do not the Stranger and Theaetetus agree in
the Sophist that it would be "monstrous and absurd" to deny that
life, motion, and soul belong to the intelligible things? Do they not indeed define being as a power to act or be
affected? Does not Socrates in the Theaetetus
entertain the same definition when he construes the world as made up of an
infinity of powers to act and be affected? Plato's dialogues do not set forth a
theory of forms. They set forth a way to get started with the work of
philosophic inquiry, and Aristotle moves altogether within that way. Much in
his writings that is a closed book to those who insist on seeing him as Plato's
opponent opens up when one lets the dialogues serve as the key.
2. Translating Aristotle
Then we shall not
hesitate to take whatever light we can find in the dialogues and shine it on
Aristotle's text at least to see if anything comes into the light. And this
brings me to a third assumption: the English word substance is of no help in
understanding Aristotle's word ousia.
The central question of theMetaphysics
is, What is ousia?
Aristotle claims that it is the same as the question, What is being? and that
it is in fact the question everyone who has ever done any philosophy or physics
has been asking. Since we do not share Aristotle's language we cannot know what
claim he is making until we find a way to translate ousia. The translators give us the word
substance only because earlier translators and commentators did so, while they
in turn did so because still earlier translators into Latin rendered it assubstantia. Early modern philosophy, in
all the European languages, is full of discussions of substance which stem from
Latin versions of Aristotle. Though oral traditions keep meanings alive this
written tradition has buried Aristotle's meaning irretrievably. We must ignore
it, and take our access to the meaning of ousia from Plato's use of it, but before we do so a quick
look at where the word substance came from may help us bury it.
The earliest
Latin translations of Aristotle tried a number of ways of translating ousia, but by the fourth century AD, when
St. Augustine lived, only two remained in use: essentia was made as a formal parallel to ousia, from the feminine singular
participle of the verb to be plus an abstract noun ending, so that the whole
would be roughly equivalent to an English translation being-ness; the second
translation,substantia, was an
attempt to get closer to ousia
by interpreting Aristotle's use of it as something like "persisting
substratum". Augustine, who had no interest in interpreting Aristotle,
thought that, while everything in the world possesses substantia, a persisting underlying
identity, the fullness of being suggested by the word essentia could belong to no created thing
but only to their creator. Aristotle, who is quite explicit on the point that
creation is impossible, believed no such thing, and Augustine didn't think he
did. But Augustine's own thinking offered a consistent way to distinguish two
Latin words whose use had become muddled. Boethius, in his commentaries on
Aristotle, followed Augustine's lead, and hence always translated ousia as substantia, and his usage seems to have settled the matter.
And so a word designed by the anti-Aristotelian Augustine to mean a low and
empty sort of being turns up in our translations of the word whose meaning
Aristotle took to be the highest and fullest sense of being. Descartes, in
his Meditations, uses the
word substance only with his tongue in his cheek; Locke explicitly analyzes it
as an empty notion of an I-don't-know-what; and soon after the word is laughed
out of the vocabulary of serious philosophic endeavor. It is no wonder that
the Metaphysics ceased to
have any influence on living thinking: its heart had been cut out of it by its
friends.
3. The Meaning of Ousia (Being) in Plato
What does ousia
mean? It is already a quirky, idiomatic word in ordinary use when Plato gets
hold of it. By a quirk of our own language one may say indeed that it means
substance, but only, I repeat only, in the sense in which a rich man is called
a man of substance. You may safely allow your daughter to marry him because you
know where he will be and what he will be doing tomorrow and twenty years from
now.Ousia meant permanent
property, real estate, non-transferable goods: not the possessions we are
always using up or consuming but those that remain--land, houses, wealth of the
kind one never spends since it breeds new wealth with no expense of itself. When
Socrates asks Meno for the ousia
of the bee he is not using a technical philosophical term but a metaphor: what
is the estate of a bee that each one inherits simply by being born a bee? A man
of substance who has permanent wealth is who he is because of what he owns. A
bee is to his permanent and his variable characteristics as a man is to his
permanent and his spendable wealth. The metaphor takes a second step when
applied to virtue: the varying instances of virtue in a man, a woman, a slave,
and the rest must all have some unvarying core which makes them virtues. There
must be some single meaning to which we always refer when we pronounce anything
a virtue. This is the step Socrates
continually insists that Meno must take. But remember, in the slave-boy scene,
Socrates twice entices the slave-boy into giving plausible incorrect answers
about the side of the double square. Is there an ousia of virtue? Socrates uses the word
not as the result of an induction or abstraction or definition, but by
stretching an already strained metaphor. People have disposable goods which
come and go and ousiatic goods which remain; bees have some characteristics in
which they differ, and others in which they share; the virtues differ, but are
they the same in anything but name? Even if they are, must it be a definition
that they share? Not all men have ousia.
Ordinarily only a few men do. The rest of us work for them, sell to them, marry
them, gather in the hills to destroy them, but do not have what they have.
Perhaps there are only a few virtues, or only one.
The word ousia, as Plato's Socrates handles it,
seems to be a double-edged weapon. It explicitly rejects Meno's way of saying
what virtue is, but implicitly suggests that the obvious alternative may fail
as well. If virtue is not simply a meaningless label used ambiguously for many
unconnected things, that does not mean that it must unambiguously name the same
content in each of the things it names. Since ousia is our metaphor, let us ask what wealth means. If a poor man has a hut and
a cow and some stored-up food, are they his wealth? He is certainly not
wealthy. On the other hand, King Lear says that "our basest beggars Are in
poorest thing superfluous"; no human life is cut so fine as to lack
anything beyond what satisfies bare need. The beggar, like the family on
welfare, does not have the means to satisfy need, but need not for that reason
forego those possessions which give life comfort or continuity. His wealth is
derived from the wealth of others. The small farmer may maintain something of
the independence a wealthy man enjoys, but one bad year could wipe him out. He
will either accumulate enough to become wealthy himself, or his life will
remain a small-scale analogy to that of the wealthy. Wealth means, first of all, only that which a few people have and the
rest of us lack, but because
it means that, it also, at the same time, means secondarily something that all
of us possess. There is an ambiguity at work in the meaning of the word
"wealth" which is not a matter of a faulty vocabulary and not a
matter of language at all: it expresses the way things are. Wealth of various
kinds exists by derivation from and analogy to wealth in the emphatic sense.
Indeed Meno, who spontaneously defines virtue by listing virtues, is equally
strongly inclined to say that the power to rule over men and possessions is the
only virtue there is. He cannot resolve the logical difficulties Socrates
raises about his answers, but they are all resolvable. Meno in fact believes
that virtue is ousia in
its simple sense of big money, and that women, children, and slaves can only
have virtue derivatively and ambiguously. Socrates' question is one of those
infuriatingly ironic games he is always playing. The ousia of virtue, according to Meno and Gorgias,
is ousia.
4. Ousia in Aristotle
When the
word ousia turns up in
texts of Aristotle, it is this hidden history of its use, and not its
etymology, which is determining its meaning. First of all, the word fills a gap
in the language of being, since Greek has no word for thing. The two closest equivalents
are to on and to chrema. To on simply means whatever
is, and includes the color blue, the length two feet, the action walking, and
anything at all that can be said to be. To
chrema means a thing used, used up, spent, or consumed; any kind of
possession, namely, that is not ousia. ousia holds together, remains, and makes
its possessor emphatically somebody. In the vocabulary of money, ousia is to to chremata as whatever remains constant
in a thing is to all theonta that come and go. ousia also carries with it the sense of
something that belongs somehow to all but directly and fully only to a few. The
word is ready-made to be the theme of Aristotle's investigation of being,
because both the word and the investigation were designed by Plato. For
Aristotle, the inquiry into the nature of being begins with the observation
that being is meant in many ways. It is like Meno's beginning, and it must be
subjected to the same Socratic questioning.
Suppose that
there is some one core of meaning to which we refer whenever we say that
something is. What is its content? Hegel says of being as being:
"it is not
to be felt, or perceived by sense, or pictured in imagination... it is mere
abstraction... the absolutely negative... just Nothing."
And isn't he
right, as Parmenides was before him? Leave aside all those characteristics in
which beings differ, and what is left behind? To Aristotle, this means that
being is not a universal or a genus. If being is the comprehensive class to
which everything belongs, how does it come to have sub-classes? It would have
to be divided with respect to something outside itself. Beings would have to be
distinguished by possessing or failing to possess some characteristic, but that
characteristic would have to be either a class within being, already separated
off from the rest by reference to something prior, or a non-being. Since both
are impossible, being must come already divided: the highest genera or ultimate
classes of things must be irreducibly many. This is Aristotle's doctrine of the
categories, and according to him being means at least eight different things.
5. The Doctrine of Categories
The categories
have familiar names: quality, quantity, relation, time, place, action,
being-acted upon. The question Socrates asked about things, What is it?, is too
broad, since it can be answered truly with respect to any of the categories
that apply, and many times in some of them. For example, I'll describe
something to you: it is backstage now; it is red; it is three feet high; it is
lying down and breathing. I could continue telling you what it is in this
fashion for as long as I pleased and you would not know what it is. It is an
Irish setter. What is different about that last answer? To be an Irish setter
is not to be a quality or quantity or time or action but to be a whole which
comprises many ways of being in those categories, and much change and
indeterminacy in them. The redness, three-foot-high-ness, respiration and much
else cohere in a thing which I have named in its thinghood by calling it an
Irish setter. Aristotle calls this way of being ousia. Aristotle's logical works reflect
upon the claims our speech makes about the world. The principal result of
Aristotle's inquiry into the logical categories of being is, I think, the claim
that the thinghood of things in the world is never reducible in our speech to
any combination of qualities, quantities, relations, actions, and so on:
that ousia or thinghood
must be a separate category. What happens when I try to articulate the being of
a thing such as an Irish setter? I define it as a dog with certain properties.
But what then is a dog? It is an animal with certain properties, and an animal
is an organism with certain properties, and an organism is a thing with the
property life. At each level I meet, as dog, animal, organism, what Aristotle
calls secondary ousia or
secondary thinghood.
I set out to give
an account of what makes a certain collection of properties cohere as a certain
thing, and I keep separating off some of them and telling you that the rest
cohere as a whole. At my last step, when I say that an organism is a
living thing, the problem
of secondary thinghood is present in its nakedness. Our speech, no matter how
scientific, must always leave the question of the hanging-together of things as
things a question.
6. The Central Question of the Metaphysics
Thus the logical
inquiries bequeath to the Metaphysics
its central question, which we are now in a position to translate. The question
that was asked of old and will always be asked by anyone who is alive enough to
wonder about anything is, What is being? What is a thing? What is the thinghood
of things? What makes our world a world of things at all? We are here at the
deepest postulate of Aristotelian philosophizing: the integrity of the world as
a world and of anything in it which endures as itself for any time at all, is
not self-explanatory, is something to be wondered at, is caused.
We are taught that a moving thing, if nothing disturbs
it, will continue moving forever. Do you believe that? It is certainly true
that a heavy thing in motion is as hard to stop as it was to set in motion, and
that we cannot step out of moving automobiles without continuing, for a while,
to share their motions. But these are evidences of persistence of motion, not
at all the same thing as inertia of motion. There is no evidence of the latter.
In principle there cannot be, because we cannot abolish all the world to
observe an undisturbed moving thing. There is a powerful and in its way,
beautiful, account of the world which assumes inertia, appealing to those
experiences which suggest that motion at an unchanging speed is a state no
different from that of rest. The hidden premise which leads from that step to
the notion of inertia is the assumption that rest is an inert state. If it is
not, the same evidence could lead to the conclusion that an unchanging speed is
a fragile and vulnerable thing, as unlikely and as hard to come by as an
unchanging anything. How can a balloon
remain unchanged? It does so only so long as the air inside pushes out no
harder and no less hard than the air outside pushes in. Is the air inside the
balloon at rest? Can it be at rest as long as it is performing a task? Can the
balloon be at rest if the air inside it cannot be? It can certainly remain in a
place, like other apparently inert things, say a table. If you pulled the legs
from under a table the top would fall, and if you removed the top the legs
would fall. Leave them together and leave them alone and they do not move, but
is the table at rest? Surely no more so than a pair of arm wrestlers, straining
every muscle but unable to budge each other, can be said to be resting. But
can't we find an inert thing anywhere in the world? How about a single lump of
rock? But if I throw it in the air it will return to find a resting place. It
seems to rest only when something blocks it, and if I let it rest on my hand or
my head, something will make me uncomfortable. Can the rock be doing nothing?
And if we cannot find inertia in a rock, where could it be? An animal is either
full of circulating and respirating or it is rotting, and the same seems true
of plants. But what in the world is not animal-like, plant-like, rock-like, or
table-like? The world contains living and non-living natural beings, and it
contains products of human making, and all of them are busy. From Aristotle's wondering and
wonderful perspective, everything in the world is busy just continuing to be
itself. This is not a "theory" of Aristotle's; it is a way of
bringing the world to sight with the questioning intellect awake. Try that way
of looking on for size: the world has nothing to lose for ceasing to be taken
for granted. Consider an analogy. Ptolemy is content to say that Venus and
Mercury happen to have the same longitudinal period as the sun and that Mars,
Jupiter, and Saturn all happen to lag just as far behind the sun in any time as
they have moved in anomaly. Copernicus, in the most passionate and convincing
part of his argument, shows that these facts can be explained. Lucretius (whom we may
substitute for Aristotle's favorite materialist, Empedocles) thought that cats
and dogs and giraffes just happened to come about by accumulation, like the
sands on the beach. Lucretius' failure to wonder at a giraffe, his reduction of
the living to the blind and dead, is, from Aristotle's standpoint, a failure to
recognize what is truly one, what is not just a heap, what is genuinely a
thing.
The least
thoughtful, least alert way of being in the world is to regard everything which
remains itself as doing so causelessly, inertly. To seek a cause for the
being-as-it-is of any thing is already to be in the grip of the question
Aristotle says must always be asked. To seek the causes and sources of the
being-as-it-is of everything that is, is to join Aristotle in his Copernican
revolution which regards every
manifestation of persistence, order, or recurrence as a marvel, an achievement.
That everything in the world disclosed to our senses is in a ceaseless state of
change, most of us would grant. That the world nevertheless hangs together
enough to be experienced at all is a fact so large that we rarely take notice
of it. But the two together--change, and a context of persistence out of which
change can emerge--force one to acknowledge some non-human cause at work: for
whichever side of the world--change or rest, order or dissolution--is simply
its uncaused, inert way, the other side must be the result of effort. Something
must be at work in the world, hidden to us, visible only in its effects,
pervading all that is, and it must be either a destroyer or a preserver.
7. The World as Cosmos
That much seems
to me to be demonstrable, but the next step is a difficult one to take because
the world presents to us two faces: the living and the non-living. The
thinghood of living things consists in organized unity, maintained through
effort, at work in a variety of activities characteristic of each species; but
a rock or a flame or some water or some dirt or some air is a thing in a much
different way, unified only by accidental boundaries, indifferent to being
divided or heaped together, at work only in some one local motion, up or down.
Which is the aberration, life or non-life? For Aristotle the choice need not be
made, since the distinction between the two forms of being only results from a
confusion. Flesh, blood, bone, and hair would seem inorganic and inanimate if
they were not organized into and animated as, say a cat. But earth, air, fire,
and water, all of it, is always organized into and animate as the cosmos. The
heavens enclose an organized body which has a size, a shape, and a hierarchical
structure all of which it maintains by ceaseless, concerted activity. You may
think that in believing this, Aristotle betrays an innocence which we cannot
recover. But not only Aristotle and Ptolemy, but also Copernicus and Kepler
believed the visible heaven to be a cosmos, and not only they, but also,
amazingly, Newton himself. In our century, Einstein calculated the volume of
the universe, and cosmology has once again become a respectable scientific
pursuit. Moderns, for whom the spherical motion of the heavens no longer
indicates that the heavens have boundaries, draw the same conclusion from the fact
that there is darkness. Anyone who would take the assertion that his outlook is
modern to include the denial that there is a cosmos would make a very shallow
claim, one having more to do with poetic fashion than with reasoned conviction.
The question of the cosmos has not been made obsolete, and the very least we
must admit is that the appearance of an inorganic, inanimate nature is not
conclusive and would result from our human-sized perspective whether there is a
cosmos or not.
If the world is a
cosmos, then it is one more instance of the kind of being that belongs to every
animal and plant in it. And if that is so, there is nothing left to display any
other kind of being. Try it: take inventory. What is there? The color red is,
only if it is the color of some thing. Color itself is, only if it is some one
color, and the color of a thing. The relation "taller than" is, only
if it is of two or more things. What has being but is not a thing must depend
on some thing for its being. But on the other hand a mere thing, mere matter as
we call it, using the word differently than Aristotle ever does, is an
impossibility too. Relatively inert, rock-like being is the being of a part of
what comes only in wholes--cosmos, plant, or animal. And all man-made things must
borrow their material from natural things and their very holding-together from
the natural tendencies of the parts of the cosmos. To be is to be alive; all
other being is borrowed being. Any comprehensive account of things must come to
terms with the special being of animals and plants: for Lucretius, living
things are not marvels but a problem which he solves by dissolving them into
the vast sea of inert purposelessness. For Aristotle, as for Plato, wonder is
not a state to be dissolved but a beckoning to be followed, and for Aristotle
the wonderful animals and plants point the way to being itself, to that
being qua being which is
the source of all being, for we see it in the world in them and only in them.
Thus when
Aristotle begins in Book 7 of the Metaphysics
to ask what makes a thing a thing, he narrows the question to apply only to
living things. All other being is, in one way or another, their effect. He is
asking for their cause. At that point, his inquiry into the causes and sources
of being itself, simply as being, merges with the inquiry in Book 2 of
his Physics, where the
question is, What is nature? The answer, as well, must be the same, and just as
Aristotle concludes that nature is form, he concludes that being is form. Does
the material of an animal make it what it is? Yes, but it cannot be the entire
or even principal cause. If there is anything that is not simply the sum of its
parts, it is an animal. It is continually making itself, by snatching suitable
material from its environment and discarding unsuitable material. Add some
sufficiently unsuitable material, like arsenic, and the sum of parts remains,
but the animal ceases to be. The whole which is not accounted for by the
enumeration of its parts is the topic of the last section of theTheaetetus, where Socrates offers several
playful images of that kind of being: a wagon, a melody, the number six, and
the example discussed at most length, which Aristotle borrows, the syllable.
8. Forms, Wholeness, and Thinghood
Aristotle insists that the syllable is never the sum
of its letters. Socrates, of course, argues both sides of the question, and
Theaetetus agrees both times. Let's try it ourselves. Take the word
"put", p-u-t. voice the letters separately, as well as you can, and
say them in succession, as rapidly as you can. I think you will find that, as
long as you attempt to add sound to sound, you will have a grunt surrounded by
two explosions of breath. When you voice the whole syllable as one sound, the a
is already present when you begin sounding the p, and the t sound is already
shaping the u. Try to pronounce the first two letters and add the third as an
afterthought, and you will get two sounds. I have tried all this, and think
it's true, but you must decide for yourself. Aristotle says that the syllable
is the letters, plus something else besides; Socrates calls the something else
a form, an eidos, while
Aristotle calls it the thinghood of the thing. When I pronounce the syllable
"put", I must have in mind the whole syllable in its wholeness before
I can voice any of its parts in such a way as to make them come out parts of
it. Now a syllable is about as transitory a being as one could imagine: it is
made of breath, and it is gone as soon as it is uttered. But a craftsman works
the same way as a maker of syllables. If he simply begins nailing and gluing
together pieces of wood, metal, and leather, he is not likely to end up with a
wagon; to do so, he must have the whole shape and work of the wagon in mind in
each of his joinings and fittings. Even
so, when he is finished, what he has produced is only held together by nails
and glue. As soon as it is made, the wagon begins falling apart, and it does so
the more, the more it is used. All the more perplexing then, is the animal or
plant. It is perpetually being made and re-made after the form of its species,
yet there is no craftsman at work on it. It is a composite of material and
form, yet it is the material in it that is constantly being used up and
replaced, while the form remains intact. The form is not in any artist's
imagination, nor can it be an accidental attribute of its material. In
the Physics, nature was
traced back to form, and in the first half of the Metaphysics all being is traced to the
same source. But what is form? Where is it? Is it a cause or is it caused? Most
important of all, does it have being alone, on its own, apart from bodies? Does
it emerge from the world of bodies, or is a body a thing impossible to be
unless a form is somehow already present for it to have? Or is there something
specious about the whole effort to make form either secondary to material or primary? Are they perhaps
equal and symmetrical aspects of being, inseparable, unranked? Just as ultimate
or first material, without any characteristics supplied by form, cannot be, why
should not a pure form, not the form of anything, be regarded as its opposite
pole and as equally impossible? Or have we perhaps stumbled on a nest of
unanswerable questions? If form is the first principle of the science of
physics, might it not be a first principle simply, behind which one cannot get,
to which one may appeal for explanation but about which one cannot inquire?
Aristotle says that if there were not things apart from bodies, physics would
be first philosophy. But he calls physics second philosophy, and half theMetaphysics lies on the other side of the questions we have
been posing. It consists in the uncovering of beings not disclosed to our
senses, beings outside of and causal with respect to what we naively and
inevitably take to be the whole world.
Aristotle marks
the center and turning point of the Metaphysics
with these words: "One must inquire about (form), for this is the greatest
impasse. Now it is agreed that some of what is perceptible arethings, and so one must search first
among these. For it is preferable to proceed toward what is better known. For learning occurs in all
things in this way: through what is by nature less known toward the things more
known. And just as in matters of action the task is to make the things that are
good completely be good for each person, from out of the things that seem good
to each, so also the task here is, from out of the things more known to one, to
make the things known by nature known to him. Now what is known and primary to
each of us is often known slightly, and has little or nothing of being;
nevertheless, from the things poorly known but known to one, one must try to
know the things that are known completely." (1029a 33 - b 11) The forest
is dark, but one cannot get out of it without passing through it, carefully,
calmly, attentively. It will do no good to move in circles. The passage just
quoted connects with the powerful first sentence of the Metaphysics: "All human beings are
by nature stretched out toward a state of knowing." Our natural condition
is one of frustration, of being unable to escape a task of which the goal is
out of reach and out of sight. Aristotle here likens our frustration as
theoretical beings to our condition as practical beings: unhappiness has causes--we achieve it by seeking things--and if we
can discover what we were seeking we might be able to make what is good ours.
Similarly, if we cannot discern the goal of wisdom, we can at least begin
examining the things that stand in our way.
9. The Being of Sensible Things
The next section of the Metaphysics, from Book 7, Chapter 4
through Book 9, is the beginning of an intense forward motion. These books are
a painstaking clarification of the being of the things disclosed to our senses.
It is here that Aristotle most heavily uses the vocabulary that is most his
own, and everything he accomplishes in these books depends on the self-evidence
of the meanings of these expressions. It is these books especially which
Latinizing translators turn into gibberish. Words like essence, individual, and
actuality must either be vague or be given arbitrary definitions. The words
Aristotle uses are neither vague nor are they conceptual constructions; they
call forth immediate, direct experiences which one must have at hand to see
what Aristotle is talking about. They are not the kinds of words that books can
explain; they are words of the kind that people must share before there can be
books. That is why understanding a sentence of Aristotle is so often something
that comes suddenly, in an insight that seems discontinuous from the puzzlement
that preceded it. It is simply a matter of directing one's gaze. We must try to
make sense of Books 7-9 because they are crucial to the intention of the Metaphysics. Aristotle has an argument
independent of those books, which he makes in Book 8 of the Physics and uses again in Book 12 of
the Metaphysics that there
must be an immortal, unchanging being, ultimately responsible for all wholeness
and orderliness in the sensible world. And
he is able to go on in Book 12 to discover a good deal about that being. One
could, then, skip from the third chapter of Book 7 to Book 12, and, having
traced being to form, trace form back to its source. Aristotle would have done
that if his whole intention had been to establish that the sensible world has a
divine source, but had he done so he would have left no foundation for
reversing the dialectical motion of his argument to understand the things in
the world on the basis of their sources. Books 7-9 provide that foundation.
The constituents
of the world we encounter with our senses are not sensations. The sensible
world is not a mosaic of sensible qualities continuous with or adjacent to one
another, but meets our gaze organized into things which stand apart, detached
from their surroundings. I can indicate one of them to you by the mere act of
pointing, because it has its own boundaries and holds them through time. I need
not trace out the limits of the region of the visual field to which I refer
your attention, because the thing thrusts itself out from, holds itself aloof
from what is visible around it, making that visible residue mere background. My
pointing therefore has an object, and it is an object because it keeps being
itself, does not change randomly or promiscuously like Proteus, but holds
together sufficiently to remain the very thing at which I pointed. This way of
being, Aristotle calls being a "this". If I want to point out to you
just this red of just this region of this shirt, I will have to do a good deal
more than just point. .A "this" as Aristotle speaks of it is what
comes forth to meet the act of pointing, is that for which à need not point and
say "not that or that or that but just this," but need do nothing but
point, since it effects its own separation from what it is not.
A table, a chair,
a rock, a painting--each is a this, but a living thing is a this in a special
way. It is the author of its own this-ness. It appropriates from its
surroundings, by eating and drinking and breathing, what it organizes into and
holds together as itself. This work of self-separation from its environment is
never finished but must go on without break if the living thing is to be at
all. Let us consider as an example of a living this, some one human being. Today
his skin is redder than usual, because he has been in the sun; there is a cut
healing on his hand because he chopped onions two days ago; he is well
educated, because, five years ago, his parents had the money and taste to send
him to Harvard. All these details, and innumerably many more, belong to this
human being. But in Aristotle's way of speaking, the details I have named are
incidental to him: he is not sunburned, wounded on the hand, or
Harvard-educated because he is a human being. He is each of those things
because his nature bumped into that of something else and left him with some
mark, more or less intended, more or less temporary, but in any case aside from
what he is on his own, self-sufficiently. What he is on his own, as a result of
the activity that makes him be at all, is: two-legged, sentient, breathing, and
all the other things he is simply as a human being. There is a difference
between all the things he happens to be and the things he necessarily is on
account of what he is. Aristotle formulates the latter, the kind of being that
belongs to a thing not by happenstance but inevitably, as the "what it
kept on being in the course of being at all" for a human being, or a duck,
or a rosebush. The phrase to en einai
is Aristotle's answer to the Socratic question, ti esti? What is a giraffe? Find some way
of articulating all the things that every giraffe always is, and you will have
defined the giraffe. What each of them is throughout its life, is the product
at any instant for any one of them, of the activity that is causing it to be.
That means that the answer to the question "What is a giraffe?", and
the answer to the question "What is this giraffe?" are the same.
Stated generally, Aristotle's claim is that a this, which is in the world on its
own, self-sufficiently, has a what-it-always-was-to-be, and is just its
what-it-always-was-to-be. This is not a commonplace thought, but it is a
comprehensible one; compare it with the translators' version, "a per-se
individual is identical with its essence."
10. Matter and Form in Aristotle
The living thing as it is present to my looking seems
to be richer, fuller, more interesting than it can possibly be when it is
reduced to a definition in speech, but this is a confusion. All that belongs to
the living thing that is not implied by the definition of its species belongs
to it externally, as a result of its accidental interactions with the other
things in its environment. The definition attempts to penetrate to what it is
in itself, by its own activity of making itself be whole and persist. There is nothing fuller than the whole, nothing
richer than the life which is the winning and expressing of that wholeness,
nothing more interesting than the struggle it is always waging unnoticed, a
whole world of priority deeper and more serious than the personal history it
must drag along with the species-drama it is constantly enacting. The reduction
of the living thing to what defines it is like the reduction of a rectangular
block of marble to the form of Hermes: less is more. Strip away the accretion
of mere facts, and what is left is that without which even those facts could
not have gained admittance into the world: the forever vulnerable foundation of
all that is in the world, the shaping, ruling form, the incessant maintenance
of which is the only meaning of the phrase self-preservation. Indeed even the
bodily material of the living thing is present in the world only as active,
only as forming itself into none of the other things it might have been but
just this one thoroughly defined animal or plant. And this, finally, is
Aristotle's answer to the question, What is form? Form is material at work
according to a persisting definiteness of kind. Aristotle's definition of the
soul in De Anima, soul is
the being-at-work-staying-the-same of an organized body, becomes the definition
of form in Book 8 of the Metaphysics,
and is, at that stage of the inquiry, his definition of being.
Book 9 spells out
the consequences of this clarification of form. Form cannot be derivative from
or equivalent with material, because material on its own must be mere
possibility. It cannot enter the world until it has achieved definiteness by
getting to work in some way, and it cannot even be thought except as the
possibility of some form. Books 7-9 demonstrate that materiality is a
subordinate way of being. The living body does not bring form into the world,
it must receive form to come into the world. Form is primary and causal, and
the original source of all being in the sensible world must be traced beyond
the sensible world, to that which confers unity on forms themselves. If forms
had no integrity of their own, the world and things could not hang together and
nothing would be. At the end of Book 9, the question of being has become the question
of formal unity, the question, What makes each form one? In the woven texture
of the organization of the Metaphysics,
what comes next, at the beginning of Book 10, is a laying out of all the ways
things may be one. Glue, nails, and rope are of no use for the problem at hand,
nor, any longer, are natural shapes and motions, which have been shown to have
a derivative sort of unity. All that is left in Aristotle's array of
possibilities is the unity of that of which the thinking or the knowing is one.
This thread of
the investigation, which we may call for convenience the biological one,
converges in Book 12 with a cosmological one. The animal and plant species take
care of their own perpetuation by way of generation, but what the parents pass
on to the offspring is an identity which must hold together thanks to a
timeless activity of thinking. The cosmos holds together in a different way: it
seems to be literally and directly eternal by way of a ceaseless repetition of
patterns of locomotion. An eternal motion cannot result from some other motion,
but must have an eternal, unchanging cause. Again, Aristotle lays out all the
possibilities. What can cause a motion without undergoing a motion? A thing
desired can, and so can a thing thought. Can you think of a third? Aristotle
says that there are only these two, and that, moreover, the first reduces to
the second. When I desire an apple it is the fleshy apple and not the thought
of it toward which I move, but it is the thought or imagining of the fleshy apple
that moves me toward the
apple. The desired object causes motion only as an object of thought. Just as
the only candidate left to be the source of unity of form among the animals and
plants was the activity of thinking, so again the only possible unmoved source
for the endless circlings of the stars is an eternal activity of thinking.
Because it is deathless and because the heavens and nature and all that is
depend upon it, Aristotle calls this activity God. Because it is always
altogether at work, nothing that is thought by it is ever outside or apart from
it: it is of thinking, simply. Again, because it is always altogether at work,
nothing of it is ever left over outside of or apart from its work of thinking:
it is thinking, simply. It is the pure holding-together of the pure
holdable-together, activity active, causality caused. The world is, in all its
being most deeply, and in its deepest being wholly, intelligible. So far is
Aristotle from simply assuming the intelligibility of things, that he requires
twelve books of argument to account for it. All being is dependent on the being
of things; among things, the artificial are derived from the natural; because
there is a cosmos, all natural things have being as living things; because all
living things depend on either a species-identity or an eternal locomotion,
there must be a self-subsisting activity of thinking.
The fact that there are a Book 13 and a Book 14 to
the Metaphysics indicates
that, in Aristotle's view, the question of being has not yet undergone its last
transformation. With the completion of Book 12, the question of being becomes:
What is the definition of the world? What is the primary intelligible structure
that implies all that is permanent in the world? Books 13 and 14 of the Metaphysics examine the only two answers
that anyone has ever proposed to that question outside of myths. They are: that
the divine thinking is a direct thinking of all the animal and plant species,
and that it is a thinking of the mathematical sources of things. The conclusions of these two books are entirely
negative. The inquiry into being itself cannot come to rest by transferring to
the divine source the species-identities which constitute the world, nor can
they be derived from their mathematical aspects. Aristotle's final
transformation of the question of being is into a question. Books 13 and 14 are
for the sake of rescuing the question as one which does not and cannot yield to
a solution but insists on being faced and thought directly. Repeatedly, through
the Metaphysics, Aristotle
says that the deepest things must be simple. One cannot speak the truth about
them, nor even ask, a question about them, because they have no parts. They
have no articulation in speech, but only contact with that which thinks. The
ultimate question of the Metaphysics,
which is at once What is all being at its roots? and What is the life of God?,
and toward which the whole Metaphysics
has been designed to clear the way, takes one beyond the limits of speech
itself. The argument of the Metaphysics
begins from our direct encounter with the sensible world, absorbs that world
completely into speech, and carries its speech to the threshold of that on
which world and speech depend. The shape of the book is a zig-zag, repeatedly
encountering the inexpressible simple things and veering away. By climbing to
that life which is the being-at-work of thinking, and then ending with a
demonstration of what that life is not, Aristotle leaves us to disclose that
life to ourselves in the only way possible, in the privacy of lived thinking.
The Metaphysics is not an
incomplete work: it is the utmost gift that a master of words can give.
11. References and Further Reading
- Aristotle, Metaphysics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Green Lion Press, 1999.
- Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Focus Philosophical Library, Pullins Press, 2002.
- Aristotle, On the Soul, Joe Sachs (trans.), Green Lion Press, 2001.
- Aristotle, Poetics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Focus Philosophical Library, Pullins Press, 2006.
- Aristotle, Physics, Joe Sachs (trans.), Rutgers U. P., 1995.
Author Information
Joe SachsEmail: joe.sachs@sjc.edu
St. John's College
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário