SÓCRATES (464 - 399 a.C.)
It was a hugely important Greek philosopher
from the Classical period (often known as the Socratic period in his honour). Unlike most of the Pre-Socratic philosophers who came before him, who were much more interested in
establishing how the world works, Socrates was more concerned with how
people should behave, and so was perhaps the first major philosopher of Ethics.
An enigmatic figure known to us only through
other people's accounts (principally the dialogues of his student Plato), he is credited as one of the founders of Western Philosophy. He is considered by some as the very antithesis
of the Sophists of his day, who claimed to have knowledge which they could
transmit to others (often for payment), arguing instead that knowledge should
be pursued for its own sake, even if one could never fully possess
it.
He made important and lasting contributions in the
fields of Ethics, Epistemology and Logic, and particularly in the methodology of philosophy (his Socratic
Method or "elenchus"). His views were instrumental
in the development of many of the major philosophical movements and schools
which came after him, including Platonism (and the Neo-Platonism and Aristotelianism it gave rise to), Cynicism, Stoicism and Hedonism.
Life
Socrates was born, as far as we know, in Athens around 469
B.C. Our knowledge of his life is sketchy and derives mainly from three
contemporary sources, the dialogues of Plato and Xenophon (c. 431 - 355 B.C.), and the plays
of Aristophanes (c. 456 - 386 B.C.). According to Plato, Socrates' father was Sophroniscus (a sculptor
and stonemason) and his mother was Phaenarete (a midwife). His family
was respectable in descent, but humble in means. He appears to
have had no more than an ordinary Greek education (reading, writing, gymnastics
and music, and, later, geometry and astronomy) before devoting his time almost
completely to intellectual interests.
He is usually described as unattractive in
appearance and short in stature, and he apparently rarely washed or
changed his clothes. But he did nevertheless marry Xanthippe, a woman
much younger than he and renowned for her shrewishness (Socrates
justified his marriage on the grounds that a horse-trainer needs to hone his
skills on the most spirited animals). She bore for him three sons, Lamprocles,
Sophroniscus and Menexenus, who were all were quite young
children at the time of their father's trial and death and, according to Aristotle, they turned out unremarkable, silly and dull.
It is not known for sure who his teachers were,
but he seems to have been acquainted with the doctrines of Parmenides, Heraclitus and Anaxagoras. Plato recorded the fact that Socrates met Zeno of Elea and Parmenides on their trip to Athens, probably in about 450 B.C. Other
influences which have been mentioned include a rhetorician named Prodicus,
a student of Anaxagoras called Archelaus, and two women (besides his
mother): Diotima (a witch and priestess from Mantinea who taught him all about "eros"
or love), and Aspasia (the mistress of the Greek statesman Pericles,
who taught him the art of funeral orations).
It is not clear how Socrates earned a living. Some
sources suggest that he continued the profession of stonemasonry from
his father. He apparently served for a time as a member of the senate of
Athens, and he served (and reportedly
distinguished himself) in the Athenian army during three campaigns at Potidaea, Amphipolis
and Delium. However, most texts seem to indicate that Socrates did
not work, devoting himself solely to discussing philosophy in the squares
of Athens.
Using a method now known as the Socratic Method (or Socratic dialogue
or dialectic), he grew famous for drawing forth knowledge from his
students by pursuing a series of questions and examining the implications
of their answers. Often he would question people's unwarranted
confidence in the truth of popular opinions, but usually without
offering them any clear alternative teaching. Aristophanes portrayed Socrates
as running a Sophist school and accepting payment for teaching,
but other sources explicitly deny this.
The best known part of Socrates' life is his trial
and execution. Despite claiming complete loyalty to his city,
Socrates' pursuit of virtue and his strict adherence to truth
clashed with the course of Athenian politics and society (particularly
in the aftermath of Athens' embarrassing defeats in the Peloponnesian War
with Sparta). Socrates raised questions about Athenian religion, but
also about Athenian democracy and, in particular, he praised Athens' arch-rival Sparta,
causing some scholars to interpret his trial as an expression of political
infighting. However, it more likely resulted from his self-appointed
position as Athens'
social and moral critic, and his insistence on trying to improve the
Athenians' sense of justice (rather than upholding the status quo and
accepting the development of immorality). His "crime"
was probably merely that his paradoxical wisdom made several prominent
Athenians look foolish in public.
Whatever the motivation, he was found guilty
(by a narrow margin of 30 votes out of the 501 jurors) of impiety and corrupting
the minds of the youth of Athens, and he was sentenced to death by
drinking a mixture containing poison hemlock in 399 B.C., at the age of
70. Although he apparently had an opportunity to escape, he chose not
to, believing that a true philosopher should have no fear of death, that
it would be against his principles to break his social contract
with the state by evading its justice, and that he would probably fare no
better elsewhere even if he were to escape into exile.
Work
As has been mentioned, Socrates himself did not
write any philosophical texts, and our knowledge of the man and his
philosophy is based on writings by his students and contemporaries,
particularly Plato's dialogues, but also the writings of Aristotle, Xenophon and Aristophanes. As these
are either the partisan philosophical texts of his supporters, or works
of dramatic rather than historically accurate intent, it is difficult to
find the “real” Socrates (often referred to as the "Socratic
problem"). In Plato's Socratic Dialogues in particular, it is well nigh impossible
to tell which of the views attributed to Socrates are actually his and
which Plato's own.
Perhaps Socrates' most important and enduring
single contribution to Western thought is his dialectical method of
inquiry, which he referred to as "elenchus" (roughly,
"cross-examination") but which has become known as the Socratic
Method or Socratic Debate (although some commentators have argued
that Protagoras actually invented the “Socratic” method). It has been
called a negative method of hypothesis elimination, in that
better hypotheses are found by steadily identifying and eliminating
those which lead to contradictions. Even today, the Socratic Method
is still used in classrooms and law schools as a way of discussing complex
topics in order to expose the underlying issues in both the subject
and the speaker. Its influence is perhaps most strongly felt today in the use
of the Scientific Method, in which the hypothesis is just the
first stage towards a proof.
At its simplest, the Socratic Method is used to solve
a problem by breaking the problem down into a series of questions, the
answers to which gradually distill better and better solutions. Both the
questioner and the questioned explore the implications of the other's
positions, in order to stimulate rational thinking and illuminate
ideas. Thus, Socrates would counter any assertion with a counterexample
which disproves the assertion (or at least shows it to be inadequate). This
would lead to a modified assertion, which Socrates would then test again
with another counterexample. Through several iterations of this kind, the
original assertion is continually adjusted and becomes more and more difficult
to refute, which Socrates held meant that it was closer and closer to the truth.
Socrates believed fervently in the immortality of
the soul, and he was convinced that the gods had singled him out as a kind
of divine emissary to persuade the people of Athens that their moral
values were wrong-headed, and that, instead of being so concerned with
their families, careers, and political responsibilities, they ought to be
worried about the "welfare of their souls". However, he also
questioned whether "arete" (or "virtue") can
actually be taught as the Sophists believed. He observed that many successful fathers (such as the
prominent military general Pericles, for example) did not produce sons
of their own quality, which suggested to him that moral excellence was more a
matter of divine bequest than parental nurture.
He often claimed that his wisdom was limited to
an awareness of his own ignorance, (although he did claim to have
knowledge of "the art of love"). Thus, he never actually claimed
to be wise, only to understand the path a lover of wisdom must take in
pursuing it. His claim that he knew one and only one thing, that he knew
nothing, may have influenced the later school of Skepticism. He
saw his role, not as a teacher or a theorist, but as analogous to a midwife
who could bring the theories of others to life, although to do so he
would of course need to have experience and knowledge of that of
which he talked. He believed that anyone could be a philosopher, not
just those who were highly trained and educated, and indeed that everyone had
a duty to ask philosophical questions (he is famously quoted as
claiming that "the unexamined life is not worth living").
Many of the beliefs traditionally attributed to the
historical Socrates have been characterized as "paradoxical"
because they seem to conflict with common sense, such as: no-one desires
evil, no-one errs or does wrong willingly or knowingly; all virtue is
knowledge; virtue is sufficient for happiness. He believed that wrongdoing
was a consequence of ignorance and those who did wrong knew no better
(sometimes referred to as Ethical Intellectualism). He believed the best way for people to live was to
focus on self-development rather than the pursuit of material wealth,
and he always invited others to try to concentrate more on friendships
and a sense of true community. He was convinced that humans possessed
certain virtues (particularly the important philosophical or
intellectual virtues), and that virtue was the most valuable of all
possessions, and the ideal life should be spent in search of the Good
(an early statement of Eudaimonism or Virtue Ethics).
Socrates' political views, as represented in Plato's dialogue "The Republic",
were strongly against the democracy that had so recently been
restored in the Athens of his day, and indeed against any form of government
that did not conform to his ideal of a perfect republic led by
philosophers, who he claimed were the only type of person suitable to
govern others. He believed that the will of the majority was not
necessarily a good method of decision-making, but that it was much more
important that decisions be logical and defensible. However, these may
be more Plato's own views than those of Socrates, "The
Republic" being a "middle period" work often considered
to be not representative of the views of the historical Socrates.
In Plato's "early" dialogue, "Apology of
Socrates", Socrates refused to pursue conventional
politics, on the grounds that he could not look into the matters of others
(or tell people how to live their lives) when he did not yet understand how to
live his own. Some have argued that he considered the rule of the "Thirty
Tyrants" (who came to power briefly during his life, led by Critias,
a relative of Plato and a one-time student of Socrates himself)
even less legitimate than the democratic senate that sentenced him to
death.
Likewise, in the dialogues of Plato, Socrates often appears to support a mystical
side, discussing reincarnation and the mystery religions (popular
religious cults of the time, such as the Eleusinian Mysteries,
restricted to those who had gone through certain secret initiation rites),
but how much of this is attributable to Socrates or to Plato himself is
not (and never will be) clear. Socrates often referred to what the Greeks
called a "daemonic sign", a kind of inner voice he
heard only when he was about to make a mistake (such as the sign that he
claimed prevented him from entering into politics). Although we would
consider this to be intuition today, Socrates thought of it as a form of
"divine madness", the sort of insanity that is a gift from
the gods and gives us poetry, mysticism, love and even
philosophy itself.
Socrates' views were instrumental in the
development of many of the major philosophical movements and schools which came
after him, particularly the Platonism of his principle student Plato, (and the Neo-Platonism and Aristotelianism it gave rise to). His idea of a life of austerity
combined with piety and morality (largely ignored by Plato and Aristotle) was essential to the core beliefs of later
schools like Cynicism and Stoicism. Socrates' stature in Western Philosophy returned in full force with the Renaissance and the Age of Reason in Europe when political theory began to
resurface under such philosophers as John Locke and Thomas Hobbes. Aristippus of Cyrene
(c. 435 - 360 B.C.), the founder of the school of Hedonism was also
a pupil of Socrates, although he rather skewed Socrates' teaching.
Socrates (469—399 B.C.E.)
Socrates is one of the few individuals whom one could say has so-shaped
the cultural and intellectual development of the world that, without him,
history would be profoundly different. He is best known for his
association with the Socratic method of question and answer, his claim that he
was ignorant (or aware of his own absence of knowledge), and his claim that the
unexamined life is not worth living, for human beings. He was the inspiration
for Plato, the thinker widely held to be the founder of the Western
philosophical tradition. Plato in turn served as the teacher of
Aristotle, thus establishing the famous triad of ancient philosophers:
Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. Unlike other philosophers of his time and ours, Socrates never
wrote anything down but was committed to living simply and to interrogating the
everyday views and popular opinions of those in his home city of Athens. At the age
of 70, he was put to death at the hands of his fellow citizens on charges of
impiety and corruption of the youth. His trial, along with the social and
political context in which occurred, has warranted as much treatment from
historians and classicists as his arguments and methods have from philosophers.
This article gives an overview of Socrates: who he was, what he thought,
and his purported method. It is both historical and philosophical.
At the same time, it contains reflections on the difficult nature of knowing
anything about a person who never committed any of his ideas to the written
word. Much of what is known about Socrates comes to us from Plato, although
Socrates appears in the works of other ancient writers as well as those who
follow Plato in the history of philosophy. This article recognizes that
finding the original Socrates may be impossible, but it attempts to achieve a
close approximation.
1. Biography: Who was Socrates?
a. The Historical Socrates
i. Birth and Early Life
Socrates was born in Athens
in the year 469 B.C.E. to Sophroniscus, a stonemason, and Phaenarete, a
midwife. His family was not extremely poor, but they were by no means wealthy,
and Socrates could not claim that he was of noble birth like Plato. He
grew up in the political deme or district of Alopece, and when he turned 18,
began to perform the typical political duties required of Athenian males.
These included compulsory military service and membership in the Assembly, the
governing body responsible for determining military strategy and legislation.
In a culture that worshipped male beauty, Socrates had the misfortune of
being born incredibly ugly. Many of our ancient sources attest to his
rather awkward physical appearance, and Plato more than once makes reference to
it (Theaetetus 143e, Symposium, 215a-c; also Xenophon Symposium
4.19, 5.5-7 and Aristophanes Clouds 362). Socrates was
exophthalmic, meaning that his eyes bulged out of his head and were not
straight but focused sideways. He had a snub nose, which made him
resemble a pig, and many sources depict him with a potbelly. Socrates did
little to help his odd appearance, frequently wearing the same cloak and sandals
throughout both the day and the evening. Plato’s Symposium (174a)
offers us one of the few accounts of his caring for his appearance.
As a young man Socrates was given an education appropriate for a person
of his station. By the middle of the 5th century B.C.E., all
Athenian males were taught to read and write. Sophroniscus, however, also took
pains to give his son an advanced cultural education in poetry, music, and
athletics. In both Plato and Xenophon, we find a Socrates that is well
versed in poetry, talented at music, and quite at-home in the gymnasium.
In accordance with Athenian custom, his father also taught him a trade, though
Socrates did not labor at it on a daily basis. Rather, he spent his days
in the agora (the Athenian marketplace), asking questions of those who
would speak with him. While he was poor, he quickly acquired a following
of rich young aristocrats—one of whom was Plato—who particularly enjoyed
hearing him interrogate those that were purported to be the wisest and most influential
men in the city.
Socrates was married to Xanthippe, and according to some sources, had a
second wife. Most suggest that he first married Xanthippe, and that she
gave birth to his first son, Lamprocles. He is alleged to have married
his second wife, Myrto, without dowry, and she gave birth to his other two
sons, Sophroniscus and Menexenus. Various accounts attribute Sophroniscus
to Xanthippe, while others even suggest that Socrates was married to both women
simultaneously because of a shortage of males in Athens at the time. In accordance with
Athenian custom, Socrates was open about his physical attraction to young men,
though he always subordinated his physical desire for them to his desire that
they improve the condition of their souls.
Socrates fought valiantly during his time in the Athenian
military. Just before the Peloponnesian War with Sparta
began in 431 B.C.E, he helped the Athenians win the battle of Potidaea (432 B.C.E.), after which he saved
the life of Alcibiades, the famous Athenian general. He also fought as
one of 7,000 hoplites aside 20,000 troops at the battle of Delium (424 B.C.E.)
and once more at the battle of Amphipolis (422 B.C.E.). Both battles were
defeats for Athens.
Despite his continued service to his city, many members of Athenian
society perceived Socrates to be a threat to their democracy, and it is this
suspicion that largely contributed to his conviction in court. It is
therefore imperative to understand the historical context in which his trial
was set.
ii. Later Life and Trial
1. The Peloponnesian War and the Threat to Democracy
Between 431—404 B.C.E. Athens fought one of its bloodiest and most
protracted conflicts with neighboring Sparta,
the war that we now know as the Peloponnesian War. Aside from the fact
that Socrates fought in the conflict, it is important for an account of his
life and trial because many of those with whom Socrates spent his time became
either sympathetic to the Spartan cause at the very least or traitors to Athens at worst.
This is particularly the case with those from the more aristocratic Athenian
families, who tended to favor the rigid and restricted hierarchy of power in Sparta instead of the more widespread democratic
distribution of power and free speech to all citizens that obtained in Athens. Plato more
than once places in the mouth of his character Socrates praise for Sparta (Protagoras
342b, Crito 53a; cf. Republic 544c in which most people think the
Spartan constitution is the best). The political regime of the Republic
is marked by a small group of ruling elites that preside over the citizens
of the ideal city.
There are a number of important historical moments throughout the war
leading up to Socrates’ trial that figure in the perception of him as a
traitor. Seven years after the battle of Amphipolis, the Athenian navy
was set to invade the island
of Sicily, when a number
of statues in the city called “herms”, dedicated to the god Hermes, protector
of travelers, were destroyed. Dubbed the ‘Mutilation of the Herms’ (415
B.C.E.), this event engendered not only a fear of those who might seek to
undermine the democracy, but those who did not respect the gods. In
conjunction with these crimes, Athens
witnessed the profanation of the Eleusinian mysteries, religious rituals that
were to be conducted only in the presence of priests but that were in this case
performed in private homes without official sanction or recognition of any
kind. Amongst those accused and persecuted on suspicion of involvement in
the crimes were a number of Socrates’ associates, including Alcibiades, who was
recalled from his position leading the expedition in Sicily. Rather than face prosecution
for the crime, Alcibiades escaped and sought asylum in Sparta.
Though Alcibiades was not the only of Socrates’ associates implicated in
the sacrilegious crimes (Charmides and Critias were suspected as well), he is
arguably the most important. Socrates had by many counts been in love
with Alcibiades and Plato depicts him pursuing or speaking of his love for him
in many dialogues (Symposium 213c-d, Protagoras 309a, Gorgias
481d, Alcibiades I 103a-104c, 131e-132a). Alcibiades is typically
portrayed as a wandering soul (Alcibiades I 117c-d), not committed to
any one consistent way of life or definition of justice. Instead, he was
a kind of cameleon-like flatterer that could change and mold himself in order
to please crowds and win political favor (Gorgias 482a). In 411
B.C.E., a group of citizens opposed to the Athenian democracy led a coup
against the government in hopes of establishing an oligarchy. Though the
democrats put down the coup later that year and recalled Alcibiades to lead the
Athenian fleet in the Hellespont, he aided the
oligarchs by securing for them an alliance with the Persian satraps.
Alcibiades therefore did not just aid the Spartan cause but allied himself with
Persian interests as well. His association with the two principal enemies
of Athens
reflected poorly on Socrates, and Xenophon tells us that Socrates’ repeated
association with and love for Alcibiades was instrumental in the suspicion that
he was a Spartan apologist.
Sparta finally defeated Athens
in 404 B.C.E., just five years before Socrates’ trial and execution.
Instead of a democracy, they installed as rulers a small group of Athenians who
were loyal to Spartan interests. Known as “The Thirty” or sometimes as
the “Thirty Tyrants”, they were led by Critias, a known associate of Socrates
and a member of his circle. Critias’ nephew Charmides, about whom we have
a Platonic dialogue of the same name, was also a member. Though Critias
put forth a law prohibiting Socrates from conducting discussions with young men
under the age of 30, Socrates’ earlier association with him—as well as his
willingness to remain in Athens and endure the rule of the Thirty rather than
flee—further contributed to the growing suspicion that Socrates was opposed to
the democratic ideals of his city.
The Thirty ruled tyrannically—executing a number of wealthy Athenians as
well as confiscating their property, arbitrarily arresting those with
democratic sympathies, and exiling many others—until they were overthrown in
403 B.C.E. by a group of democratic exiles returning to the city. Both
Critias and Charmides were killed and, after a Spartan-sponsored peace accord,
the democracy was restored. The democrats proclaimed a general amnesty in
the city and thereby prevented politically motivated legal prosecutions aimed
at redressing the terrible losses incurred during the reign of the
Thirty. Their hope was to maintain unity during the reestablishment of
their democracy.
One of Socrates’ main accusers, Anytus, was one of the democratic exiles
that returned to the city to assist in the overthrow of the Thirty.
Plato’s Meno, set in the year 402 B.C.E., imagines a conversation
between Socrates and Anytus in which the latter argues that any citizen of
Athens can teach virtue, an especially democratic view insofar as it assumes
knowledge of how to live well is not the restricted domain of the esoteric
elite or privileged few. In the discussion, Socrates argues that if one
wants to know about virtue, one should consult an expert on virtue (Meno
91b-94e). The political turmoil of the city, rebuilding itself as a
democracy after nearly thirty years of destruction and bloodshed, constituted a
context in which many citizens were especially fearful of threats to their
democracy that came not from the outside, but from within their own city.
While many of his fellow citizens found considerable evidence against
Socrates, there was also historical evidence in addition to his military
service for the case that he was not just a passive but an active supporter of
the democracy. For one thing, just as he had associates that were known
oligarchs, he also had associates that were supporters of the democracy,
including the metic family of Cephalus and Socrates’ friend Chaerephon, the man
who reported that the oracle at Delphi had proclaimed that no man was wiser
than Socrates. Additionally, when he was ordered by the Thirty to help
retrieve the democratic general Leon
from the island
of Salamis for execution,
he refused to do so. His refusal could be understood not as the defiance
of a legitimately established government but rather his allegiance to the
ideals of due process that were in effect under the previously instituted
democracy. Indeed, in Plato’s Crito, Socrates refuses to escape
from prison on the grounds that he lived his whole life with an implied
agreement with the laws of the democracy (Crito 50a-54d).
Notwithstanding these facts, there was profound suspicion that Socrates was a
threat to the democracy in the years after the end of the Peloponnesian
War. But because of the amnesty, Anytus and his fellow accusers Meletus
and Lycon were prevented from bringing suit against Socrates on political
grounds. They opted instead for religious grounds.
2. Greek Religion and Socrates’ Impiety
Because of the amnesty the charges made against Socrates were framed in
religious terms. As recounted by Diogenes Laertius (1.5.40), the charges
were stated as follows: “Socrates does criminal wrong by not recognizing the
gods that the city recognizes, and furthermore by introducing new divinities;
and he also does criminal wrong by corrupting the youth” (other accounts:
Xenophon Memorabilia I.I.1 and Apology 11-12, Plato, Apology
24b and Euthyphro 2c-3b). Many people understood the charge about
corrupting the youth to signify that Socrates taught his subversive views to
others, a claim that he adamantly denies in his defense speech by claiming that
he has no wisdom to teach (Plato, Apology 20c) and that he cannot be
held responsible for the actions of those that heard him speak (Plato, Apology 33a-c).
It is now customary to refer to the principal written accusation on the
deposition submitted to the Athenian court as an accusation of impiety, or
unholiness. Rituals, ceremonies, and sacrifices that were officially
sanctioned by the city and its officials marked ancient Greek religion.
The sacred was woven into the everyday experience of citizens who demonstrated
their piety by correctly observing their ancestral traditions.
Interpretation of the gods at their temples was the exclusive domain of priests
appointed and recognized by the city. The boundary and separation between
the religious and the secular that we find in many countries today therefore
did not obtain in Athens.
A religious crime was consequently an offense not just against the gods, but
also against the city itself.
Socrates and his contemporaries lived in a polytheistic society, a
society in which the gods did not create the world but were themselves
created. Socrates would have been brought up with the stories of the gods
recounted in Hesiod and Homer, in which the gods were not omniscient,
omnibenevolent, or eternal, but rather power-hungry super-creatures that
regularly intervened in the affairs of human beings. One thinks for
example of Aphrodite saving Paris from death at the hands of Menelaus (Homer,
Iliad 3.369-382) or Zeus sending Apollo to rescue the corpse of Sarpedon
after his death in battle (Homer, Iliad 16.667-684). Human beings
were to fear the gods, sacrifice to them, and honor them with festivals and
prayers.
Socrates instead seemed to have a conception of the divine as always
benevolent, truthful, authoritative, and wise. For him, divinity always
operated in accordance with the standards of rationality. This conception
of divinity, however, dispenses with the traditional conception of prayer and
sacrifice as motivated by hopes for material payoff. Socrates’ theory of
the divine seemed to make the most important rituals and sacrifices in the city
entirely useless, for if the gods are all good, they will benefit human beings
regardless of whether or not human beings make offerings to them. Jurors
at his trial might have thought that, without the expectation of material
reward or protection from the gods, Socrates was disconnecting religion from
its practical roots and its connection with the civic identity of the city.
While Socrates was critical of blind acceptance of the gods and the
myths we find in Hesiod and Homer, this in itself was not unheard of in Athens at the time.
Solon, Xenophanes, Heraclitus, and Euripides had all spoken against the
capriciousness and excesses of the gods without incurring penalty. It is
possible to make the case that Socrates’ jurors might not have indicted him
solely on questioning the gods or even of interrogating the true meaning of
piety. Indeed, there was no legal definition of piety in Athens at the time, and jurors were therefore
in a similar situation to the one in which we find Socrates in Plato’s Euthyphro,
that is, in need of an inquiry into what the nature of piety truly is.
What seems to have concerned the jurors was not only Socrates’ challenge to the
traditional interpretation of the gods of the city, but his seeming allegiance
to an entirely novel divine being, unfamiliar to anyone in the city.
This new divine being is what is known as Socrates’ daimon.
Though it has become customary to think of a daimon as a spirit or
quasi-divinity (for example, Symposium 202e-203a), in ancient Greek
religion it was not solely a specific class of divine being but rather a mode
of activity, a force that drives a person when no particular divine agent can
be named (Burkett, 180). Socrates claimed to have heard a sign or voice
from his days as a child that accompanied him and forbid him to pursue certain
courses of action (Plato, Apology 31c-d, 40a-b, Euthydemus
272e-273a, Euthyphro 3b, Phaedrus 242b, Theages 128-131a, Theaetetus
150c-151b, Rep 496c; Xenophon, Apology 12, Memorabilia
1.1.3-5). Xenophon adds that the sign also issued positive commands (Memorablia
1.1.4, 4.3.12, 4.8.1, Apology 12). This sign was accessible
only to Socrates, private and internal to his own mind. Whether Socrates
received moral knowledge of any sort from the sign is a matter of scholarly
debate, but beyond doubt is the strangeness of Socrates’ insistence that he
took private instructions from a deity that was unlicensed by the city.
For all the jurors knew, the deity could have been hostile to Athenian
interests. Socrates’ daimon was therefore extremely influential in his
indictment on the charge of worshipping new gods unknown to the city (Plato, Euthyphro
3b, Xenophon, Memorabilia I.1.2).
Whereas in Plato’s Apology Socrates makes no attempt to reconcile
his divine sign with traditional views of piety, Xenophon’s Socrates argues
that just as there are those who rely on birdcalls and receive guidance from
voices, so he too is influenced by his daimon. However, Socrates had no
officially sanctioned religious role in the city. As such, his attempt to
assimilate himself to a seer or necromancer appointed by the city to interpret
divine signs actually may have undermined his innocence, rather than help to
establish it. His insistence that he had direct, personal access to the
divine made him appear guilty to enough jurors that he was sentenced to death.
b. The Socratic Problem: the Philosophical Socrates
The Socratic problem is the problem faced by historians of philosophy
when attempting to reconstruct the ideas of the original Socrates as distinct
from his literary representations. While we know many of the historical
details of Socrates’ life and the circumstances surrounding his trial, Socrates’
identity as a philosopher is much more difficult to establish. Because he
wrote nothing, what we know of his ideas and methods comes to us mainly from
his contemporaries and disciples.
There were a number of Socrates’ followers who wrote conversations in
which he appears. These works are what are known as the logoi
sokratikoi, or Socratic accounts. Aside from Plato and Xenophon, most
of these dialogues have not survived. What we know of them comes to us
from other sources. For example, very little survives from the dialogues
of Antisthenes, whom Xenophon reports as one of Socrates’ leading
disciples. Indeed, from polemics written by the rhetor Isocrates, some
scholars have concluded that he was the most prominent Socratic in Athens for the first
decade following Socrates’ death. Diogenes Laertius (6.10-13) attributes
to Antisthenes a number of views that we recognize as Socratic, including that
virtue is sufficient for happiness, the wise man is self-sufficient, only the
virtuous are noble, the virtuous are friends, and good things are morally fine
and bad things are base.
Aeschines of Sphettus wrote seven dialogues, all of which have been
lost. It is possible for us to reconstruct the plots of two of them: the Alcibiades—in
which Socrates shames Alcibiades into admitting he needs Socrates’ help to be
virtuous—and the Aspasia—in which Socrates recommends the famous wife of
Pericles as a teacher for the son of Callias. Aeschines’ dialogues focus
on Socrates’ ability to help his interlocutor acquire self-knowledge and better
himself.
Phaedo of Elis wrote two dialogues. His central use of Socrates is
to show that philosophy can improve anyone regardless of his social class or
natural talents. Euclides of Megara wrote six dialogues, about which we
know only their titles. Diogenes Laertius reports that he held that the
good is one, that insight and prudence are different names for the good, and
that what is opposed to the good does not exist. All three are Socratic
themes. Lastly, Aristippus of Cyrene wrote no Socratic dialogues but is
alleged to have written a work entitled To Socrates.
The two Socratics on whom most of our philosophical understanding of
Socrates depends are Plato and Xenophon. Scholars also rely on the works
of the comic playwright Aristophanes and Plato’s most famous student,
Aristotle.
i. Origin of the Socratic Problem
The Socratic problem first became pronounced in the early 19th
century with the influential work of Friedrich Schleiermacher. Until this
point, scholars had largely turned to Xenophon to identify what the historical
Socrates thought. Schleiermacher argued that Xenophon was not a
philosopher but rather a simple citizen-soldier, and that his Socrates was so
dull and philosophically uninteresting that, reading Xenophon alone, it would
be difficult to understand the reputation accorded Socrates by so many of his
contemporaries and nearly all the schools of philosophy that followed
him. The better portrait of Socrates, Schleiermacher claimed, comes to us
from Plato.
Though many scholars have since jettisoned Xenophon as a legitimate
source for representing the philosophical views of the historical Socrates,
they remain divided over the reliability of the other three sources. For
one thing, Aristophanes was a comic playwright, and therefore took considerable
poetic license when scripting his characters. Aristotle, born 15 years
after Socrates’ death, hears about Socrates primarily from Plato. Plato himself
wrote dialogues or philosophical dramas, and thus cannot be understood to be
presenting his readers with exact replicas or transcriptions of conversations
that Socrates actually had. Furthermore, many scholars think that Plato’s
so-called middle and late dialogues do not present the views of the historical
Socrates.
We therefore see the difficult nature of the Socratic problem: because
we don’t seem to have any consistently reliable sources, finding the true
Socrates or the original Socrates proves to be an impossible task. What
we are left with, instead, is a composite picture assembled from various
literary and philosophical components that give us what we might think of as
Socratic themes or motifs.
ii. Aristophanes
Born in 450 B.C.E., Aristophanes wrote a number of comic plays intended
to satirize and caricature many of his fellow Athenians. His Clouds
(423 B.C.E.) was so instrumental in parodying Socrates and painting him as a
dangerous intellectual capable of corrupting the entire city that Socrates felt
compelled in his trial defense to allude to the bad reputation he acquired as a
result of the play (Plato, Apology 18a-b, 19c). Aristophanes was
much closer in age to Socrates than Plato and Xenophon, and as such is the only
one of our sources exposed to Socrates in his younger years.
In the play, Socrates is the head of a phrontistêrion, a school of
learning where students are taught the nature of the heavens and how to win
court cases. Socrates appears in a swing high above the stage,
purportedly to better study the heavens. His patron deities, the clouds,
represent his interest in meteorology and may also symbolize the lofty nature
of reasoning that may take either side of an argument. The main plot of
the play centers on an indebted man called Strepsiades, whose son Phidippides
ends up in the school to learn how to help his father avoid paying off his
debts. By the end of the play, Phidippides has beaten his father, arguing
that it is perfectly reasonable to do so on the grounds that, just as it is
acceptable for a father to spank his son for his own good, so it is acceptable
for a son to hit a father for his own good. In addition to the theme that
Socrates corrupts the youth, we therefore also find in the Clouds the
origin of the rumor that Socrates makes the stronger argument the weaker and
the weaker argument the stronger. Indeed, the play features a
personification of the Stronger Argument—which represents traditional education
and values—attacked by the Weaker Argument—which advocates a life of pleasure.
While the Clouds is Aristophanes’ most famous and comprehensive
attack on Socrates, Socrates appears in other of his comedies as well. In
the Birds (414 B.C.E.), Aristophanes coins a Greek verb based on
Socrates’ name to insinuate that Socrates was truly a Spartan sympathizer
(1280-83). Young men who were found “Socratizing” were expressing their
admiration of Sparta
and its customs. And in the Frogs (405), the Chorus claims that it
is not refined to keep company with Socrates, who ignores the poets and wastes
time with ‘frivolous words’ and ‘pompous word-scraping’ (1491-1499).
Aristophanes’ Socrates is a kind of variegated caricature of trends and
new ideas emerging in Athens
that he believed were threatening to the city. We find a number of such
themes prevalent in Presocratic philosophy and the teachings of the Sophists,
including those about natural science, mathematics, social science, ethics,
political philosophy, and the art of words. Amongst other things,
Aristophanes was troubled by the displacement of the divine through scientific explanations
of the world and the undermining of traditional morality and custom by
explanations of cultural life that appealed to nature instead of the
gods. Additionally, he was reticent about teaching skill in disputation,
for fear that a clever speaker could just as easily argue for the truth as
argue against it. These issues constitute what is sometimes called the
“new learning” developing in 5th century B.C.E. Athens, for which
the Aristophanic Socrates is the iconic symbol.
iii. Xenophon
Born in the same decade as Plato (425 B.C.E.), Xenophon lived in the
political deme of Erchia. Though he knew Socrates he would not have had
as much contact with him as Plato did. He was not present in the
courtroom on the day of Socrates’ trial, but rather heard an account of it
later on from Hermogenes, a member of Socrates’ circle. His depiction of
Socrates is found principally in four works: Apology—in which Socrates
gives a defense of his life before his jurors—Memorabilia—in which
Xenophon himself explicates the charges against Socrates and tries to defend
him—Symposium—a conversation between Socrates and his friends at a
drinking party—and Oeconomicus—a Socratic discourse on estate
management. Socrates also appears in Xenophon’s Hellenica and Anabasis.
Xenophon’s reputation as a source on the life and ideas of Socrates is
one on which scholars do not always agree. Largely thought to be a
significant source of information about Socrates before the 19th
century, for most of the 20th century Xenophon’s ability to depict
Socrates as a philosopher was largely called into question. Following
Schleiermacher, many argued that Xenophon himself was either a bad philosopher
who did not understand Socrates, or not a philosopher at all, more concerned
with practical, everyday matters like economics. However, recent
scholarship has sought to challenge this interpretation, arguing that it
assumes an understanding of philosophy as an exclusively speculative and
critical endeavor that does not attend to the ancient conception of philosophy
as a comprehensive way of life.
While Plato will likely always remain the principal source on Socrates
and Socratic themes, Xenophon’s Socrates is distinct in philosophically
interesting ways. He emphasizes the values of self-mastery (enkrateia),
endurance of physical pain (karteria), and self-sufficiency (autarkeia).
For Xenophon’s Socrates, self-mastery or moderation is the foundation of virtue
(Memorabilia, 1.5.4). Whereas in Plato’s Apology the oracle
tells Chaerephon that no one is wiser than Socrates, in Xenophon’s Apology
Socrates claims that the oracle told Chaerephon that “no man was more free than
I, more just, and more moderate” (Xenophon, Apology, 14).
Part of Socrates’ freedom consists in his freedom from want, precisely
because he has mastered himself. As opposed to Plato’s Socrates,
Xenophon’s Socrates is not poor, not because he has much, but because he needs
little. Oeconomicus 11.3 for instance shows Socrates displeased with
those who think him poor. One can be rich even with very little on the
condition that one has limited his needs, for wealth is just the excess of what
one has over what one requires. Socrates is rich because what he has is
sufficient for what he needs (Memorabilia 1.2.1, 1.3.5, 4.2.38-9).
We also find Xenophon attributing to Socrates a proof of the existence
of God. The argument holds that human beings are the product of an
intelligent design, and we therefore should conclude that there is a God who is
the maker (dēmiourgos) or designer of all things (Memorabilia
1.4.2-7). God creates a systematically ordered universe and governs it in
the way our minds govern our bodies (Memorabilia 1.4.1-19,
4.3.1-18). While Plato’s Timaeus tells the story of a dēmiourgos
creating the world, it is Timaeus, not Socrates, who tells the story.
Indeed, Socrates speaks only sparingly at the beginning of the dialogue, and
most scholars do not count as Socratic the cosmological arguments therein.
iv. Plato
Plato was Socrates’ most famous disciple, and the majority of what most
people know about Socrates is known about Plato’s Socrates. Plato was
born to one of the wealthiest and politically influential families in Athens in 427 B.C.E., the
son of Ariston and Perictione. His brothers were Glaucon and Adeimantus, who
are Socrates’ principal interlocutors for the majority of the Republic.
Though Socrates is not present in every Platonic dialogue, he is in the
majority of them, often acting as the main interlocutor who drives the
conversation.
The attempt to extract Socratic views from Plato’s texts is itself a
notoriously difficult problem, bound up with questions about the order in which
Plato composed his dialogues, one’s methodological approach to reading them,
and whether or not Socrates, or anyone else for that matter, speaks for
Plato. Readers interested in the details of this debate should consult “Plato.” Generally
speaking, the predominant view of Plato’s Socrates in the English-speaking
world from the middle to the end of the 20th century was simply that
he was Plato’s mouthpiece. In other words, anything Socrates says in the
dialogues is what Plato thought at the time he wrote the dialogue. This
view, put forth by the famous Plato scholar Gregory Vlastos, has been
challenged in recent years, with some scholars arguing that Plato has no
mouthpiece in the dialogues (see Cooper xxi-xxiii). While we can
attribute to Plato certain doctrines that are consistent throughout his corpus,
there is no reason to think that Socrates, or any other speaker, always and
consistently espouses these doctrines.
The main interpretive obstacle for those seeking the views of Socrates
from Plato is the question of the order of the dialogues. Thrasyllus, the
1st century (C.E.) Platonist who was the first to arrange the
dialogues according to a specific paradigm, organized the dialogues into nine
tetralogies, or groups of four, on the basis of the order in which he believed
they should be read. Another approach, customary for most scholars by the
late 20th century, groups the dialogues into three categories on the
basis of the order in which Plato composed them. Plato begins his career,
so the narrative goes, representing his teacher Socrates in typically short
conversations about ethics, virtue, and the best human life. These are
“early” dialogues. Only subsequently does Plato develop his own
philosophical views—the most famous of which is the doctrine of the Forms or
Ideas—that Socrates defends. These “middle” dialogues put forth positive
doctrines that are generally thought to be Platonic and not Socratic. Finally,
towards the end of his life, Plato composes dialogues in which Socrates
typically either hardly features at all or is altogether absent. These
are the “late” dialogues.
There are a number of complications with this interpretive thesis, and
many of them focus on the portrayal of Socrates. Though the Gorgias is
an early dialogue, Socrates concludes the dialogue with a myth that some
scholars attribute to a Pythagorean influence on Plato that he would not have
had during Socrates’ lifetime. Though the Parmenides is a middle
dialogue, the younger Socrates speaks only at the beginning before Parmenides
alone speaks for the remainder of the dialogue. While the Philebus
is a late dialogue, Socrates is the main speaker. Some scholars identify
the Meno as an early dialogue because Socrates refutes Meno’s attempts
to articulate the nature of virtue. Others, focusing on Socrates’ use of
the theory of recollection and the method of hypothesis, argue that it is a
middle dialogue. Finally, while Plato’s most famous work the Republic
is a middle dialogue, some scholars make a distinction within the Republic itself.
The first book, they argue, is Socratic, because in it we find Socrates
refuting Thrasymachus’ definition of justice while maintaining that he knows
nothing about justice. The rest of the dialogue they claim, with its
emphasis on the division of the soul and the metaphysics of the Forms, is
Platonic.
To discern a consistent Socrates in Plato is therefore a difficult
task. Instead of speaking about chronology of composition, contemporary
scholars searching for views that are likely to have been associated with the
historical Socrates generally focus on a group of dialogues that are united by
topical similarity. These “Socratic dialogues” feature Socrates as the
principal speaker, challenging his interlocutor to elaborate on and critically
examine his own views while typically not putting forth substantive claims of
his own. These dialogues—including those that some scholars think are not
written by Plato and those that most scholars agree are not written by Plato
but that Thrasyllus included in his collection—are as follows: Euthyphro,
Apology, Crito, Alcibiades I, Alcibiades II, Hipparchus,
Rival Lovers, Theages, Charmides, Laches, Lysis,
Euthydemus, Protagoras, Gorgias, Meno, Greater
Hippias, Lesser Hippias, Ion, Menexenus, Clitophon,
Minos. Some of the more famous positions Socrates defends in these
dialogues are covered in the content section.
v. Aristotle
Aristotle was born in 384 B.C.E., 15 years after the death of
Socrates. At the age of eighteen, he went to study at Plato’s Academy,
and remained there for twenty years. Afterwards, he traveled throughout Asia and was invited by Phillip II of Macedon to tutor
his son Alexander, known to history as Alexander the Great. While
Aristotle would never have had the chance to meet Socrates, we have in his
writings an account of both Socrates’ method and the topics about which he had
conversations. Given the likelihood that Aristotle heard about Socrates
from Plato and those at his Academy, it is not surprising that most of what he
says about Socrates follows the depiction of him in the Platonic dialogues.
Aristotle related four concrete points about Socrates. The first
is that Socrates asked questions without supplying an answer of his own,
because he claimed to know nothing (De Elenchis Sophisticus
1836b6-8). The picture of Socrates here is consistent with that of
Plato’s Apology. Second, Aristotle claims that Socrates never
asked questions about nature, but concerned himself only with ethical
questions. Aristotle thus attributes to the historical Socrates both the
method and topics we find in Plato’s Socratic dialogues.
Third, Aristotle claims that Socrates is the first to have employed epagōgē,
a word typically rendered in English as “induction.” This translation,
however, is misleading, lest we impute to Socrates a preference for inductive
reasoning as opposed to deductive reasoning. The term better indicates
that Socrates was fond or arguing via the use of analogy. For instance,
just as a doctor does not practice medicine for himself but for the best
interest of his patient, so the ruler in the city takes no account of his own
personal profit, but is rather interested in caring for his citizens (Republic
342d-e).
The fourth and final claim Aristotle makes about Socrates itself has two
parts. First, Socrates was the first to ask the question, ti esti:
what is it? For example, if someone were to suggest to Socrates that our
children should grow up to be courageous, he would ask, what is courage?
That is, what is the universal definition or nature that holds for all examples
of courage? Second, as distinguished from Plato, Socrates did not
separate universals from their particular instantiations. For Plato, the
noetic object, the knowable thing, is the separate universal, not the
particular. Socrates simply asked the “what is it” question (on this and
the previous two points, see Metaphysics I.6.987a29-b14; cf. b22-24,
b27-33, and see XIII.4.1078b12-34).
2. Content: What does Socrates Think?
Given the nature of these sources, the task of recounting what Socrates
thought is not an easy one. Nonetheless, reading Plato’s Apology,
it is possible to articulate a number of what scholars today typically
associate with Socrates. Plato the author has his Socrates claim that
Plato was present in the courtroom for Socrates’ defense (Apology 34a),
and while this cannot mean that Plato records the defense as a word for word
transcription, it is the closest thing we have to an account of what Socrates
actually said at a concrete point in his life.
a. Presocratic Philosophy and the Sophists
Socrates opens his defense speech by defending himself against his older
accusers (Apology 18a), claiming they have poisoned the minds of his
jurors since they were all young men. Amongst these accusers was
Aristophanes. In addition to the claim that Socrates makes the worse
argument into the stronger, there is a rumor that Socrates idles the day away
talking about things in the sky and below the earth. His reply is that he
never discusses such topics (Apology 18a-c). Socrates is
distinguishing himself here not just from the sophists and their alleged
ability to invert the strength of arguments, but from those we have now come to
call the Presocratic philosophers.
The Presocratics were not just those who came before Socrates, for there
are some Presocratic philosophers who were his contemporaries. The term
is sometimes used to suggest that, while Socrates cared about ethics, the
Presocratic philosophers did not. This is misleading, for we have
evidence that a number of Presocratics explored ethical issues. The term
is best used to refer to the group of thinkers whom Socrates did not influence
and whose fundamental uniting characteristic was that they sought to explain
the world in terms of its own inherent principles. The 6th cn.
Milesian Thales, for instance, believed that the fundamental principle of all
things was water. Anaximander believed the principle was the indefinite (apeiron),
and for Anaxamines it was air. Later in Plato’s Apology (26d-e),
Socrates rhetorically asks whether Meletus thinks he is prosecuting Anaxagoras,
the 5th cn. thinker who argued that the universe was originally a
mixture of elements that have since been set in motion by Nous, or
Mind. Socrates suggests that he does not engage in the same sort of
cosmological inquiries that were the main focus of many Presocratics.
The other group against which Socrates compares himself is the Sophists,
learned men who travelled from city to city offering to teach the youth for a
fee. While he claims he thinks it an admirable thing to teach as Gorgias,
Prodicus, or Hippias claim they can (Apology 20a), he argues that he
himself does not have knowledge of human excellence or virtue (Apology
20b-c). Though Socrates inquires after the nature of virtue, he does not
claim to know it, and certainly does not ask to be paid for his conversations.
b. Socratic Themes in Plato’s Apology
i. Socratic Ignorance
Plato’s Socrates moves next to explain the reason he has acquired the
reputation he has and why so many citizens dislike him. The oracle at Delphi told Socrates’ friend Chaerephon, “no one is wiser
than Socrates” (Apology 21a). Socrates explains that he was not
aware of any wisdom he had, and so set out to find someone who had wisdom in
order to demonstrate that the oracle was mistaken. He first went to the
politicians but found them lacking wisdom. He next visited the poets and
found that, though they spoke in beautiful verses, they did so through divine
inspiration, not because they had wisdom of any kind. Finally, Socrates
found that the craftsmen had knowledge of their own craft, but that they
subsequently believed themselves to know much more than they actually
did. Socrates concluded that he was better off than his fellow citizens
because, while they thought they knew something and did not, he was aware of
his own ignorance. The god who speaks through the oracle, he says, is truly
wise, whereas human wisdom is worth little or nothing (Apology 23a).
This awareness of one’s own absence of knowledge is what is known as
Socratic ignorance, and it is arguably the thing for which Socrates is most
famous. Socratic ignorance is sometimes called simple ignorance, to be
distinguished from the double ignorance of the citizens with whom Socrates
spoke. Simple ignorance is being aware of one’s own ignorance, whereas
double ignorance is not being aware of one’s ignorance while thinking that one
knows. In showing many influential figures in Athens that they did not know what they
thought they did, Socrates came to be despised in many circles.
It is worth nothing that Socrates does not claim here that he knows
nothing. He claims that he is aware of his ignorance and that whatever it
is that he does know is worthless. Socrates has a number of strong
convictions about what makes for an ethical life, though he cannot articulate
precisely why these convictions are true. He believes for instance that
it is never just to harm anyone, whether friend or enemy, but he does not, at
least in Book I of the Republic, offer a systematic account of the
nature of justice that could demonstrate why this is true. Because of his
insistence on repeated inquiry, Socrates has refined his convictions such that
he can both hold particular views about justice while maintaining that he does
not know the complete nature of justice.
We can see this contrast quite clearly in Socrates’ cross-examination of
his accuser Meletus. Because he is charged with corrupting the youth,
Socrates inquires after who it is that helps the youth (Apology,
24d-25a). In the same way that we take a horse to a horse trainer to
improve it, Socrates wants to know the person to whom we take a young person to
educate him and improve him. Meletus’ silence condemns him: he has never
bothered to reflect on such matters, and therefore is unaware of his ignorance
about matters that are the foundation of his own accusation (Apology
25b-c). Whether or not Socrates—or Plato for that matter—actually thinks
it is possible to achieve expertise in virtue is a subject on which scholars
disagree.
ii. Priority of the Care of the Soul
Throughout his defense speech (Apology 20a-b, 24c-25c, 31b, 32d,
36c, 39d) Socrates repeatedly stresses that a human being must care for his
soul more than anything else (see also Crito 46c-47d, Euthyphro
13b-c, Gorgias 520a4ff). Socrates found that his fellow citizens
cared more for wealth, reputation, and their bodies while neglecting their
souls (Apology 29d-30b). He believed that his mission from the god
was to examine his fellow citizens and persuade them that the most important
good for a human being was the health of the soul. Wealth, he insisted, does
not bring about human excellence or virtue, but virtue makes wealth and
everything else good for human beings (Apology 30b).
Socrates believes that his mission of caring for souls extends to the
entirety of the city of Athens.
He argues that the god gave him to the city as a gift and that his mission is
to help improve the city. He thus attempts to show that he is not guilty
of impiety precisely because everything he does is in response to the oracle
and at the service of the god. Socrates characterizes himself as a gadfly
and the city as a sluggish horse in need of stirring up (Apology
30e). Without philosophical inquiry, the democracy becomes stagnant and
complacent, in danger of harming itself and others. Just as the gadfly is
an irritant to the horse but rouses it to action, so Socrates supposes that his
purpose is to agitate those around him so that they begin to examine
themselves. One might compare this claim with Socrates’ assertion in the Gorgias
that, while his contemporaries aim at gratification, he practices the true
political craft because he aims at what is best (521d-e). Such comments,
in addition to the historical evidence that we have, are Socrates’ strongest
defense that he is not only not a burden to the democracy but a great asset to
it.
iii. The Unexamined Life
After the jury has convicted Socrates and sentenced him to death, he
makes one of the most famous proclamations in the history of philosophy.
He tells the jury that he could never keep silent, because “the unexamined life
is not worth living for human beings” (Apology 38a). We find here
Socrates’ insistence that we are all called to reflect upon what we believe,
account for what we know and do not known, and generally speaking to seek out,
live in accordance with, and defend those views that make for a well lived and
meaningful life.
Some scholars call attention to Socrates’ emphasis on human nature here,
and argue that the call to live examined lives follows from our nature as human
beings. We are naturally directed by pleasure and pain. We are
drawn to power, wealth and reputation, the sorts of values to which Athenians
were drawn as well. Socrates’ call to live examined lives is not
necessarily an insistence to reject all such motivations and inclinations but
rather an injunction to appraise their true worth for the human soul. The
purpose of the examined life is to reflect upon our everyday motivations and
values and to subsequently inquire into what real worth, if any, they
have. If they have no value or indeed are even harmful, it is upon us to
pursue those things that are truly valuable.
One can see in reading the Apology that Socrates examines the
lives of his jurors during his own trial. By asserting the primacy of the
examined life after he has been convicted and sentenced to death, Socrates, the
prosecuted, becomes the prosecutor, surreptitiously accusing those who
convicted him of not living a life that respects their own humanity. He
tells them that by killing him they will not escape examining their
lives. To escape giving an account of one’s life is neither possible nor
good, Socrates claims, but it is best to prepare oneself to be as good as
possible (Apology 39d-e).
We find here a conception of a well-lived life that differs from one
that would likely be supported by many contemporary philosophers. Today,
most philosophers would argue that we must live ethical lives (though what this
means is of course a matter of debate) but that it is not necessary for
everyone to engage in the sort of discussions Socrates had everyday, nor must
one do so in order to be considered a good person. A good person, we
might say, lives a good life insofar as he does what is just, but he does not
necessarily need to be consistently engaged in debates about the nature of
justice or the purpose of the state. No doubt Socrates would disagree,
not just because the law might be unjust or the state might do too much or too
little, but because, insofar as we are human beings, self-examination is always
beneficial to us.
c. Other Socratic Positions and Arguments
In addition to the themes one finds in the Apology, the following
are a number of other positions in the Platonic corpus that are typically
considered Socratic.
i. Unity of Virtue; All Virtue is Knowledge
In the Protagoras (329b-333b) Socrates argues for the view that
all of the virtues—justice, wisdom, courage, piety, and so forth—are one.
He provides a number of arguments for this thesis. For example, while it
is typical to think that one can be wise without being temperate, Socrates
rejects this possibility on the grounds that wisdom and temperance both have
the same opposite: folly. Were they truly distinct, they would each have
their own opposites. As it stands, the identity of their opposites
indicates that one cannot possess wisdom without temperance and vice versa.
This thesis is sometimes paired with another Socratic, view, that is,
that virtue is a form of knowledge (Meno 87e-89a; cf. Euthydemus
278d-282a). Things like beauty, strength, and health benefit human
beings, but can also harm them if they are not accompanied by knowledge or
wisdom. If virtue is to be beneficial it must be knowledge, since all the
qualities of the soul are in themselves neither beneficial not harmful, but are
only beneficial when accompanied by wisdom and harmful when accompanied by
folly.
ii. No One Errs Knowingly/No One Errs Willingly
Socrates famously declares that no one errs or makes mistakes knowingly
(Protagoras 352c, 358b-b). Here we find an example of Socrates’
intellectualism. When a person does what is wrong, their failure to do
what is right is an intellectual error, or due to their own ignorance about
what is right. If the person knew what was right, he would have done
it. Hence, it is not possible for someone simultaneously know what is right
and do what is wrong. If someone does what is wrong, they do so because
they do not know what is right, and if they claim the have known what was right
at the time when they committed the wrong, they are mistaken, for had they
truly known what was right, they would have done it.
Socrates therefore denies the possibility of akrasia, or weakness
of the will. No one errs willingly (Protagoras 345c4-e6).
While it might seem that Socrates is equivocating between knowingly and
willingly, a look at Gorgias 466a-468e helps clarify his thesis.
Tyrants and orators, Socrates tells Polus, have the least power of any member
of the city because they do not do what they want. What they do is not
good or beneficial even though human beings only want what is good or
beneficial. The tyrant’s will, corrupted by ignorance, is in such a state
that what follows from it will necessarily harm him. Conversely, the will
that is purified by knowledge is in such a state that what follows from it will
necessarily be beneficial.
iii. All Desire is for the Good
One of the premises of the argument just mentioned is that human beings
only desire the good. When a person does something for the sake of
something else, it is always the thing for the sake of which he is acting that
he wants. All bad things or intermediate things are done not for
themselves but for the sake of something else that is good. When a tyrant
puts someone to death, for instance, he does this because he thinks it is
beneficial in some way. Hence his action is directed towards the good
because this is what he truly wants (Gorgias 467c-468b).
A similar version of this argument is in the Meno, 77b-78b.
Those that desire bad things do not know that they are truly bad; otherwise,
they would not desire them. They do not naturally desire what is bad but
rather desire those things that they believe to be good but that are in fact
bad. They desire good things even though they lack knowledge of what is
actually good.
iv. It is Better to Suffer an Injustice Than to Commit One
Socrates infuriates Polus with the argument that it is better to suffer
an injustice than commit one (Gorgias 475a-d). Polus agrees that
it is more shameful to commit an injustice, but maintains it is not
worse. The worst thing, in his view, is to suffer injustice.
Socrates argues that, if something is more shameful, it surpasses in either
badness or pain or both. Since committing an injustice is not more
painful than suffering one, committing an injustice cannot surpass in pain or
both pain and badness. Committing an injustice surpasses suffering an
injustice in badness; differently stated, committing an injustice is worse than
suffering one. Therefore, given the choice between the two, we should
choose to suffer rather than commit an injustice.
This argument must be understood in terms of the Socratic emphasis on
the care of the soul. Committing an injustice corrupts one’s soul, and
therefore committing injustice is the worst thing a person can do to himself
(cf. Crito 47d-48a, Republic I 353d-354a). If one commits
injustice, Socrates goes so far as to claim that it is better to seek
punishment than avoid it on the grounds that the punishment will purge or
purify the soul of its corruption (Gorgias 476d-478e).
v. Eudaimonism
The Greek word for happiness is eudaimonia, which signifies not
merely feeling a certain way but being a certain way. A different way of
translating eudaimonia is well-being. Many scholars believe that Socrates
holds two related but not equivalent principles regarding eudaimonia: first,
that it is rationally required that a person make his own happiness the
foundational consideration for his actions, and second, that each person does
in fact pursue happiness as the foundational consideration for his
actions. In relation to Socrates’ emphasis on virtue, it is not entirely
clear what that means. Virtue could be identical to happiness—in which
case there is no difference between the two and if I am virtuous I am by
definition happy—virtue could be a part of happiness—in which case if I am
virtuous I will be happy although I could be made happier by the addition of
other goods—or virtue could be instrumental for happiness—in which case if I am
virtuous I might be happy (and I couldn’t be happy without virtue), but there
is no guarantee that I will be happy.
There are a number of passages in the Apology that seem to
indicate that the greatest good for a human being is having philosophical
conversation (36b-d, 37e-38a, 40e-41c). Meno 87c-89a suggests that
knowledge of the good guides the soul toward happiness (cf. Euthydemus
278e-282a). And at Gorgias 507a-c Socrates suggests that the
virtuous person, acting in accordance with wisdom, attains happiness (cf. Gorgias
478c-e: the happiest person has no badness in his soul).
vi. Ruling is An Expertise
Socrates is committed to the theme that ruling is a kind of craft or art
(technē). As such, it requires knowledge. Just as a doctor
brings about a desired result for his patient—health, for instance—so the ruler
should bring about some desired result in his subject (Republic 341c-d,
342c). Medicine, insofar as it has the best interest of its patient in
mind, never seeks to benefit the practitioner. Similarly, the ruler’s job
is to act not for his own benefit but for the benefit of the citizens of the
political community. This is not to say that there might not be some
contingent benefit that accrues to the practitioner; the doctor, for instance,
might earn a fine salary. But this benefit is not intrinsic to the
expertise of medicine as such. One could easily conceive of a doctor that
makes very little money. One cannot, however, conceive of a doctor that
does not act on behalf of his patient. Analogously, ruling is always for
the sake of the ruled citizen, and justice, contra the famous claim from
Thrasymachus, is not whatever is in the interest of the ruling power (Republic
338c-339a).
d. Socrates the Ironist
The suspicion that Socrates is an ironist can mean a number of things:
on the one hand, it can indicate that Socrates is saying something with the
intent to convey the opposite meaning. Some readers for instance, including
a number in the ancient world, understood Socrates’ avowal of ignorance in
precisely this way. Many have interpreted Socrates’ praise of Euthyphro,
in which he claims that he can learn from him and will become his pupil, as an
example of this sort of irony (Euthyphro 5a-b). On the other hand,
the Greek word eirōneia was understood to carry with it a sense of
subterfuge, rendering the sense of the word something like masking with the
intent to deceive.
Additionally, there are a number of related questions about Socrates’
irony. Is the interlocutor supposed to be aware of the irony, or is
he ignorant of it? Is it the job of the reader to discern the
irony? Is the purpose of irony rhetorical, intended to maintain Socrates’
position as the director of the conversation, or pedagogical, meant to encourage
the interlocutor to learn something? Could it be both?
Scholars disagree on the sense in which we ought to call Socrates
ironic. When Socrates asks Callicles to tell him what he means by the
stronger and to go easy on him so that he might learn better, Callicles claims
he is being ironic (Gorgias 489e). Thrasymachus accuses Socrates
of being ironic insofar as he pretends he does not have an account of justice,
when he is actually hiding what he truly thinks (Republic 337a).
And though the Symposium is generally not thought to be a “Socratic”
dialogue, we there find Alcibiades accusing Socrates of being ironic insofar as
he acts like he is interested in him but then deny his advances (Symposium
216e, 218d). It is not clear which kind of irony is at work with these
examples.
Aristotle defines irony as an attempt at self-deprecation (Nicomachean
Ethics 4.7, 1127b23-26). He argues that self-deprecation is the
opposite of boastfulness, and people that engage in this sort of irony do so to
avoid pompousness and make their characters more attractive. Above all,
such people disclaim things that bring reputation. On this reading,
Socrates was prone to understatement.
There are some thinkers for whom Socratic irony is not just restricted
to what Socrates says. The 19th century Danish philosopher
Søren Kierkegaard held the view that Socrates himself, his character, is
ironic. The 20th century philosopher Leo Strauss defined irony
as the noble dissimulation of one’s worth. On this reading, Socrates’
irony consisted in his refusal to display his superiority in front of his
inferiors so that his message would be understood only by the privileged
few. As such, Socratic irony is intended to conceal Socrates’ true
message.
3. Method: How Did Socrates Do Philosophy?
As famous as the Socratic themes are, the Socratic method is equally
famous. Socrates conducted his philosophical activity by means of
question an answer, and we typically associate with him a method called the elenchus.
At the same time, Plato’s Socrates calls himself a midwife—who has no ideas of
his own but helps give birth to the ideas of others—and proceeds
dialectically—defined either as asking questions, embracing the practice of
collection and division, or proceeding from hypotheses to first principles.
a. The Elenchus: Socrates the Refuter
A typical Socratic elenchus is a cross-examination of a particular
position, proposition, or definition, in which Socrates tests what his
interlocutor says and refutes it. There is, however, great debate amongst
scholars regarding not only what is being refuted but also whether or not the
elenchus can prove anything. There are questions, in other words, about
the topic of the elenchus and its purpose or goal.
i. Topic
Socrates typically begins his elenchus with the question, “what is
it”? What is piety, he asks Euthyphro. Euthyphro appears to give
five separate definitions of piety: piety is proceeding against whomever does
injustice (5d-6e), piety is what is loved by the gods (6e-7a), piety is what is
loved by all the gods (9e), the godly and the pious is the part of the just
that is concerned with the care of the gods (12e), and piety is the knowledge
of sacrificing and praying (13d-14a). For some commentators, what
Socrates is searching for here is a definition. Other commentators argue
that Socrates is searching for more than just the definition of piety but seeks
a comprehensive account of the nature of piety. Whatever the case,
Socrates refutes the answer given to him in response to the ‘what is it’ question.
Another reading of the Socratic elenchus is that Socrates is not just
concerned with the reply of the interlocutor but is concerned with the
interlocutor himself. According to this view, Socrates is as much
concerned with the truth or falsity of propositions as he is with the
refinement of the interlocutor’s way of life. Socrates is concerned with
both epistemological and moral advances for the interlocutor and himself.
It is not propositions or replies alone that are refuted, for Socrates does not
conceive of them dwelling in isolation from those that hold them. Thus
conceived, the elenchus refutes the person holding a particular view, not just
the view. For instance, Socrates shames Thrasymachus when he shows him
that he cannot maintain his view that justice is ignorance and injustice is
wisdom (Republic I 350d). The elenchus demonstrates that
Thrasymachus cannot consistently maintain all his claims about the nature of
justice. This view is consistent with a view we find in Plato’s late
dialogue called the Sophist, in which the Visitor from Elea,
not Socrates, claims that the soul will not get any advantage from learning
that it is offered to it until someone shames it by refuting it (230b-d).
ii. Purpose
In terms of goal, there are two common interpretations of the
elenchus. Both have been developed by scholars in response to what
Gregory Vlastos called the problem of the Socratic elenchus. The problem
is how Socrates can claim that position W is false, when the only thing he has
established is its inconsistency with other premises whose truth he has not
tried to establish in the elenchus.
The first response is what is called the constructivist position.
A constructivist argues that the elenchus establishes the truth or falsity of
individual answers. The elenchus on this interpretation can and does have
positive results. Vlastos himself argued that Socrates not only
established the inconsistency of the interlocutor’s beliefs by showing their
inconsistency, but that Socrates’ own moral beliefs were always consistent,
able to withstand the test of the elenchus. Socrates could therefore pick
out a faulty premise in his elenctic exchange with an interlocutor, and sought
to replace the interlocutor’s false beliefs with his own.
The second response is called the non-constructivist position.
This position claims that Socrates does not think the elenchus can establish
the truth or falsity of individual answers. The non-constructivist argues
that all the elenchus can show is the inconsistency of W with the premises X,
Y, and Z. It cannot establish that ~W is the case, or for that matter
replace any of the premises with another, for this would require a separate
argument. The elenchus establishes the falsity of the conjunction of W,
X, Y, and Z, but not the truth or falsity of any of those premises
individually. The purpose of the elenchus on this interpretation is to
show the interlocutor that he is confused, and, according to some scholars, to
use that confusion as a stepping stone on the way to establishing a more
consistent, well-formed set of beliefs.
b. Maieutic: Socrates the Midwife
In Plato’s Theaetetus Socrates identifies himself as a midwife
(150b-151b). While the dialogue is not generally considered Socratic,
it is elenctic insofar as it tests and refutes Theaetetus’ definitions of
knowledge. It also ends without a conclusive answer to its question, a
characteristic it shares with a number of Socratic dialogues.
Socrates tells Theaetetus that his mother Phaenarete was a midwife
(149a) and that he himself is an intellectual midwife. Whereas the craft
of midwifery (150b-151d) brings on labor pains or relieves them in order to
help a woman deliver a child, Socrates does not watch over the body but over
the soul, and helps his interlocutor give birth to an idea. He then
applies the elenchus to test whether or not the intellectual offspring is a
phantom or a fertile truth. Socrates stresses that both he and actual
midwives are barren, and cannot give birth to their own offspring. In
spite of his own emptiness of ideas, Socrates claims to be skilled at bringing
forth the ideas of others and examining them.
c. Dialectic: Socrates the Constructer
The method of dialectic is thought to be more Platonic than Socratic,
though one can understand why many have associated it with Socrates
himself. For one thing, the Greek dialegesthai ordinarily means
simply “to converse” or “to discuss.” Hence when Socrates is
distinguishing this sort of discussion from rhetorical exposition in the Gorgias,
the contrast seems to indicate his preference for short questions and answers
as opposed to longer speeches (447b-c, 448d-449c).
There are two other definitions of dialectic in the Platonic
corpus. First, in the Republic, Socrates distinguishes between
dianoetic thinking, which makes use of the senses and assumes hypotheses, and
dialectical thinking, which does not use the senses and goes beyond hypotheses
to first principles (Republic VII 510c-511c, 531d-535a). Second,
in the Phaedrus, Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus,
dialectic is defined as a method of collection and division. One collects
things that are scattered into one kind and also divides each kind according to
its species (Phaedrus 265d-266c).
Some scholars view the elenchus and dialectic as fundamentally different
methods with different goals, while others view them as consistent and
reconcilable. Some even view them as two parts of one argument procedure,
in which the elenchus refutes and dialectic constructs.
4. Legacy: How Have Other Philosophers Understood Socrates?
Nearly every school of philosophy in antiquity had something positive to
say about Socrates, and most of them drew their inspiration from him.
Socrates also appears in the works of many famous modern
philosophers. Immanuel Kant, the 18th century German
philosopher best known for the categorical imperative, hailed Socrates, amongst
other ancient philosophers, as someone who didn’t just speculate but who lived
philosophically. One of the more famous quotes about Socrates is from John
Stuart Mill, the 19th century utilitarian philosopher who claimed
that it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better
to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. The following is but a
brief survey of Socrates as he is treated in philosophical thinking that
emerges after the death of Aristotle in 322 B.C.E.
a. Hellenistic Philosophy
i. The Cynics
The Cynics greatly admired Socrates, and traced their philosophical lineage back to
him. One of the first representatives of the Socratic legacy was the
Cynic Diogenes of Sinope. No genuine writings of Diogenes have survived
and most of our evidence about him is anecdotal. Nevertheless, scholars
attribute a number of doctrines to him. He sought to undermine convention
as a foundation for ethical values and replace it with nature. He
understood the essence of human being to be rational, and defined happiness as
freedom and self-mastery, an objective readily accessible to those who trained
the body and mind.
ii. The Stoics
There is a biographical story according to which Zeno, the founder of
the Stoic school and not the Zeno
of Zeno's Paradoxes, became interested in philosophy by reading and inquiring
about Socrates. The Stoics took themselves to be authentically Socratic,
especially in defending the unqualified restriction of ethical goodness to
ethical excellence, the conception of ethical excellence as a kind of
knowledge, a life not requiring any bodily or external advantage nor ruined by
any bodily disadvantage, and the necessity and sufficiency of ethical
excellence for complete happiness.
Zeno is known for his characterization of the human good as a smooth
flow of life. Stoics were therefore attracted to the Socratic elenchus
because it could expose inconsistencies—both social and psychological—that
disrupted one’s life. In the absence of justification for a specific
action or belief, one would not be in harmony with oneself, and therefore would
not live well. On the other hand, if one held a position that survived
cross-examination, such a position would be consistent and coherent. The
Socratic elenchus was thus not just an important social and psychological test,
but also an epistemological one. The Stoics held that knowledge was a
coherent set of psychological attitudes, and therefore a person holding
attitudes that could withstand the elenchus could be said to have
knowledge. Those with inconsistent or incoherent psychological
commitments were thought to be ignorant.
Socrates also figures in Roman Stoicism, particularly in the works of
Seneca and Epictetus. Both men admired Socrates’ strength of
character. Seneca praises Socrates for his ability to remain consistent
unto himself in the face of the threat posed by the Thirty Tyrants, and also
highlights the Socratic focus on caring for oneself instead of fleeing oneself
and seeking fulfillment by external means. Epictetus, when offering
advice about holding to one’s own moral laws as inviolable maxims, claims,
“though you are not yet a Socrates, you ought, however, to live as one desirous
of becoming a Socrates” (Enchiridion 50).
One aspect of Socrates to which Epictetus was particularly attracted was
the elenchus. Though his understanding of the process is in some ways
different from Socrates’, throughout his Discourses Epictetus repeatedly
stresses the importance of recognition of one’s ignorance (2.17.1) and
awareness of one’s own impotence regarding essentials (2.11.1). He
characterizes Socrates as divinely appointed to hold the elenctic position
(3.21.19) and associates this role with Socrates’ protreptic expertise
(2.26.4-7). Epictetus encouraged his followers to practice the elenchus
on themselves, and claims that Socrates did precisely this on account of his
concern with self-examination (2.1.32-3).
iii. The Skeptics
Broadly speaking, skepticism is the view that we ought to be either suspicious of claims to
epistemological truth or at least withhold judgment from affirming absolute
claims to knowledge. Amongst Pyrrhonian skeptics, Socrates appears at
times like a dogmatist and at other times like a skeptic or inquirer. On
the one hand, Sextus Empiricus lists Socrates as a thinker who accepts the
existence of god (Against the Physicists, I.9.64) and then recounts the
cosmological argument that Xenophon attributes to Socrates (Against the
Physicists, I.9.92-4). On the other hand, in arguing that human being
is impossible to conceive, Sextus Empiricus cites Socrates as unsure whether or
not he is a human being or something else (Outlines of Pyrrhonism
2.22). Socrates is also said to have remained in doubt about this
question (Against the Professors 7.264).
Academic skeptics grounded their position that nothing can be known in
Socrates’ admission of ignorance in the Apology (Cicero, On the Orator 3.67, Academics
1.44). Arcesilaus, the first head of the Academy to take it toward a
skeptical turn, picked up from Socrates the procedure of arguing, first asking
others to give their positions and then refuting them (Cicero, On Ends
2.2, On the Orator 3.67, On the Nature of the Gods 1.11).
While the Academy would eventually move away from skepticism, Cicero, speaking on behalf of the Academy of Philo,
makes the claim that Socrates should be understood as endorsing the claim that
nothing, other than one’s own ignorance, could be known (Academics
2.74).
iv. The Epicurean
The Epicureans were one of the few schools that criticized Socrates, though many
scholars think that this was in part because of their animus toward their Stoic
counterparts, who admired him. In general, Socrates is depicted in
Epicurean writings as a sophist, rhetorician, and skeptic who ignored natural
science for the sake of ethical inquiries that concluded without answers.
Colotes criticizes Socrates’ statement in the Phaedrus (230a) that he
does not know himself (Plutarch, Against Colotes 21 1119b), and
Philodemus attacks Socrates’ argument in the Protagoras (319d) that
virtue cannot be taught (Rhetoric I 261, 8ff).
The Epicureans wrote a number of books against several of Plato’s
Socratic dialogues, including the Lysis, Euthydemus, and Gorgias.
In the Gorgias we find Socrates suspicious of the view that pleasure is
intrinsically worthy and his insistence that pleasure is not the equivalent of
the good (Gorgias 495b-499b). In defining pleasure as freedom from
disturbance (ataraxia) and defining this sort of pleasure as the sole
good for human beings, the Epicureans shared little with the unbridled hedonism
Socrates criticizes Callicles for embracing. Indeed, in the Letter to
Menoeceus, Epicurus explicitly argues against pursuing this sort of pleasure
(131-132). Nonetheless, the Epicureans did equate pleasure with the good,
and the view that pleasure is not the equivalent of the good could not have
endeared Socrates to their sentiment.
Another reason for the Epicurean refusal to praise Socrates or make him
a cornerstone of their tradition was his perceived irony. According to Cicero, Epicurus was
opposed to Socrates’ representing himself as ignorant while simultaneously
praising others like Protagoras, Hippias, Prodicus, and Gorgias (Rhetoric,
Vol. II, Brutus 292). This irony for the Epicureans was pedagogically
pointless: if Socrates had something to say, he should have said it instead of
hiding it.
v. The Peripatetics
Aristotle’s followers, the Peripatetics, either said little about Socrates or were pointedly
vicious in their attacks. Amongst other things, the Peripatetics accused
Socrates of being a bigamist, a charge that appears to have gained so much
traction that the Stoic Panaetius wrote a refutation of it (Plutarch, Aristides
335c-d). The general peripatetic criticism of Socrates, similar in one
way to the Epicureans, was that he concentrated solely on ethics, and that this
was an unacceptable ideal for the philosophical life.
b. Modern Philosophy
i. Hegel
In Socrates, Hegel found what he called the great historic turning point (Philosophy of
History, 448). With Socrates, Hegel claims, two opposed rights came
into collision: the individual consciousness and the universal law of the
state. Prior to Socrates, morality for the ancients was present but it
was not present Socratically. That is, the good was present as a
universal, without its having had the form of the conviction of the individual
in his consciousness (407). Morality was present as an immediate
absolute, directing the lives of citizens without their having reflected upon
it and deliberated about it for themselves. The law of the state, Hegel
claims, had authority as the law of the gods, and thus had a universal validity
that was recognized by all (408).
In Hegel’s view the coming of Socrates signals a shift in the
relationship between the individual and morality. The immediate now had
to justify itself to the individual consciousness. Hegel thus not only
ascribes to Socrates the habit of asking questions about what one should do but
also about the actions that the state has prescribed. With Socrates,
consciousness is turned back within itself and demands that the law should
establish itself before consciousness, internal to it, not merely outside it
(408-410). Hegel attributes to Socrates a reflective questioning
that is skeptical, which moves the individual away from unreflective obedience
and into reflective inquiry about the ethical standards of one’s community.
Generally, Hegel finds in Socrates a skepticism that renders ordinary or
immediate knowledge confused and insecure, in need of reflective certainty
which only consciousness can bring (370). Though he attributes to the
sophists the same general skeptical comportment, in Socrates Hegel locates
human subjectivity at a higher level. With Socrates and onward we have
the world raising itself to the level of conscious thought and becoming object
for thought. The question as to what Nature is gives way to the question
about what Truth is, and the question about the relationship of self-conscious
thought to real essence becomes the predominant philosophical issue (450-1).
ii. Kierkegaard
Kierkegaard’s most well
recognized views on Socrates are from his dissertation, The Concept of Irony
With Continual Reference to Socrates. There, he argues that Socrates
is not the ethical figure that the history of philosophy has thought him to be,
but rather an ironist in all that he does. Socrates does not just speak
ironically but is ironic. Indeed, while most people have found
Aristophanes’ portrayal of Socrates an obvious exaggeration and caricature,
Kierkegaard goes so far as to claim that he came very close to the truth in his
depiction of Socrates. He rejects Hegel’s picture of Socrates ushering in
a new era of philosophical reflection and instead argues that the limits of
Socratic irony testified to the need for religious faith. As opposed to
the Hegelian view that Socratic irony was an instrument in the service of the
development of self-consciousness, Kierkegaard claims that irony was Socrates’
position or comportment, and that he did not have any more than this to give.
Later in his writing career Kierkegaard comes to think that he has
neglected Socrates’ significance as an ethical and religious figure. In
his final essay entitled My Task, Kierkegaard claims that his mission is
a Socratic one; that is, in his task to reinvigorate a Christianity that remained
the cultural norm but had, in Kierkegaard’s eyes, nearly ceased altogether to
be practiced authentically, Kierkegaard conceives of himself as a kind of
Christian Socrates, rousing Christians from their complacency to a conception
of Christian faith as the highest, most passionate expression of individual
subjectivity. Kierkegaard therefore sees himself as a sort of Christian
gadfly. The Socratic call to become aware of one’s own ignorance finds
its parallel in the Kierkegaardian call to recognize one’s own failing to truly
live as a Christian. The Socratic claim to ignorance—while Socrates is
closer to knowledge than his contemporaries—is replaced by the Kierkegaard’s
claim that he is not a Christian—though certainly more so than his own contemporaries.
iii. Nietzsche
Nietzsche’s most famous
account of Socrates is his scathing portrayal in The Birth of Tragedy,
in which Socrates and rational thinking lead to the emergence of an age of
decadence in Athens.
The delicate balance in Greek culture between the Apollonian—order, calmness,
self-control, restraint—and the Dionysian—chaos, revelry, self-forgetfulness,
indulgence— initially represented on stage in the tragedies of Aeschylus and
Sophocles, gave way to the rationalism of Euripides. Euripides, Nietzsche
argues, was only a mask for the newborn demon called Socrates (section
12). Tragedy—and Greek culture more generally—was corrupted by “aesthetic
Socratism”, whose supreme law, Nietzsche argues, was that ‘to be beautiful
everything must be intelligible’. Whereas the former sort of tragedy
absorbed the spectator in the activities and sufferings of its chief
characters, the emergence of Socrates heralded the onset of a new kind of
tragedy in which this identification is obstructed by the spectators having to
figure out the meaning and presuppositions of the characters’ suffering.
Nietzsche continues his attack on Socrates later in his career in Twilight
of the Idols. Socrates here represents the lowest class of people
(section 3), and his irony consists in his being an exaggeration at the same
time as he conceals himself (4). He is the inventor of dialectic (5)
which he wields mercilessly because, being an ugly plebeian, he had no other
means of expressing himself (6) and therefore employed question and answer to
render his opponent powerless (7). Socrates turned dialectic into a new
kind of contest (8), and because his instincts had turned against each other
and were in anarchy (9), he established the rule of reason as a counter-tyrant
in order not to perish (10). Socrates’ decadence here consists in his
having to fight his instincts (11). He was thus profoundly anti-life, so
much so that he wanted to die (12).
Nonetheless, while Nietzsche accuses Socrates of decadence, he
nevertheless recognizes him as a powerful individual, which perhaps accounts
for why we at times find in Nietzsche a hesitant admiration of Socrates.
He calls Socrates one of the very greatest instinctive forces (The Birth of
Tragedy, section 13), labels him as a “free spirit” (Human, All Too
Human I, 433) praises him as the first “philosopher of life” in his 17th
lecture on the Preplatonics, and anoints him a ‘virtuoso of life’ in his
notebooks from 1875. Additionally, contra Twilight of the Idols,
in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche speaks of a death in which one’s
virtue still shines, and some commentators have seen in this a celebration of
the way in which Socrates died.
iv. Heidegger
Heidegger finds in Socrates
a kinship with his own view that the truth of philosophy lies in a certain way
of seeing things, and thus is identical with a particular kind of method.
He attributes to Socrates the view that the truth of some subject matter shows
itself not in some definition that is the object or end of a process of
inquiry, but in the very process of inquiry itself. Heidegger
characterizes the Socratic method as a kind of productive negation: by refuting
that which stands in front of it—in Socrates’ case, an interlocutor’s
definition—it discloses the positive in the very process of questioning.
Socrates is not interested in articulating propositions about piety but rather
concerned with persisting in a questioning relation to it that preserves its
irreducible sameness. Behind multiple examples of pious action is Piety,
and yet Piety is not something that can be spoken of. It is that which
discloses itself through the process of silent interrogation.
It is precisely in his emphasis on silence that Heidegger diverges from
Socrates. Where Socrates insisted on the give and take of question and
answer, Heideggerian questioning is not necessarily an inquiry into the views
of others but rather an openness to the truth that one maintains without the
need to speak. To remain in dialogue with a given phenomenon is not the
same thing as conversing about it, and true dialogue is always silent.
v. Gadamer
As Heidegger’s student, Gadamer shares his fundamental view that truth and method
cannot be divorced in philosophy. At the same time, his hermeneutics
leads him to argue for the importance of dialectic as conversation.
Gadamer claims that whereas philosophical dialectic presents the whole truth by
superceding all its partial propositions, hermeneutics too has the task of
revealing a totality of meaning in all its relations. The distinguishing
characteristic of Gadamer’s hermeneutical dialectic is that it recognizes
radical finitude: we are always already in an open-ended dialogical
situation. Conversation with the interlocutor is thus not a distraction
that leads us away from seeing the truth but rather is the site of truth.
It is for this reason that Gadamer claims Plato communicated his
philosophy only in dialogues: it was more than just an homage to Socrates, but
was a reflection of his view that the word find its confirmation in another and
in the agreement of another.
Gadamer also sees in the Socratic method an ethical way of being.
That is, he does not just think that Socrates converses about ethics but that
repeated Socratic conversation is itself indicative of an ethical
comportment. On this account, Socrates knows the good not because he can
give some final definition of it but rather because of his readiness to give an
account of it. The problem of not living an examined life is not that we
might live without knowing what is ethical, but because without asking
questions as Socrates does, we will not be ethical.
5. References and Further Reading
- Ahbel-Rappe, Sara, and Rachana Kamtekar (eds.), A Companion to Socrates (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006).
- Arrowsmith, William, Lattimore, Richmond, and Parker, Douglass (trans.), Four Plays by Aristophanes: The Clouds, The Birds, Lysistrata, The Frogs (New York: Meridian, 1994).
- Barnes, Jonathan, Complete Works of Aristotle vols. 1 & 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).
- Benson, Hugh H. (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
- Brickhouse, Thomas C. & Smith, Nicholas D., Plato’s Socrates (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994).
- Burkert, Walter, Greek Religion (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985).
- Cooper, John M., Plato: Collected Works (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997).
- Guthrie, W.K.C., Socrates (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971).
- Kahn, Charles H., Plato and the Socratic Dialogue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
- Kraut, Richard (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
- Morrison, Donald R., The Cambridge Companion to Socrates (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
- Rudebusch, George, Socrates (Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009).
- Santas, Gerasimos, Socrates: Philosophy in Plato’s Early Dialogues (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979).
- Taylor, C.C.W, 1998, Socrates (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998).
- Vlastos, Gregory, Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
- Xenophon: Memorabilia. Oeconomicus. Symposium. Apologia. (Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1923).
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário