Galeno (130 - 200)
Galen was one of the most prominent ancient physicians
as well as a philosopher (though most of his philosophical writings are lost). Nonetheless,
his philosophical interests are quite evident in his practice of biological
science. Galen made some key anatomical observations (though most of these were
on other primates). However, this inclination toward observation moved
his theory into the class of critical empiricism.
Galen was also a well-read scholar who combined
extensive erudition with ‘cutting edge’ observational practice to completely
change the understanding and teaching of medicine. He frequently integrates his
observational practice with the natural philosophy of Plato and
Aristotle. His position as the leading authority in medical theory
extended for at least fourteen hundred years.
Galen correctly saw that there is a methodological
difference between taking account of the patient in front of you in all of the
patient’s particularity and, instead, understanding the patient in front of you
as representing an instance of
a general rule of biomedical science. The way that Galen sought to insert
himself into this debate makes his conclusions relevant to medicine today.
Table of Contents
- Life
- Hellenistic Schools of Medicine
- Method
- Galen's Critical Empiricism
- References and Further Reading
1. Life
Galen of Pergamum was a physician who was born in Pergamum was a bustling
and vibrant city at the time and was particularly famous for its statue of
Asclepius, a god of healing. Throughout Galen's life, he avowed a devotion to
Asclepius. The city also had a library that almost rivaled Alexandria's in its size. Galen's father,
Nicon, was a prosperous architect. This allowed Galen the leisure to get an
education and choose a path of life unencumbered by the need to earn money. However,
this affluence did not mean that Galen was brought up "soft" (as per
Plato's discussion in the Republic 544b-570e in which he discusses the
devolution of political systems due to the decay of personal arête). Galen's education was broad and
directed by his father. Galen studied in mathematics (a particular favorite of
his father), grammar, logic, and philosophy--that included inquiry into the
four major schools of the time: the Platonists, the Peripatetics, the Stoics, and the Epicureans. This pluralistic
sensibility influenced the philosophical/scientific method of Galen. According
to pluralism, one should look at all the prevalent theories and then make up
one's own mind choosing either one of the theories or perhaps a new mixture of
those presented according to their strengths.
Galen began his study of medicine around the age of
sixteen when his father had a dream suggesting this direction. Galen traveled
to Smyrna and Corinth to study with both a Rationalist and with an Empiricist. When
Galen's father died, Galen traveled to Egypt (Alexandria) where he lived for
perhaps five years (152-157). What Galen might have studied in Alexandria is
highly speculative. However, Galen, himself, later declares that students
should "look at the human skeleton with your own eyes. This is very easy
in Alexandria, so that the physicians of that area instruct their pupils with
the aid of autopsy" (Kühn II, 220, translation L. Edelstein). This
quotation points to the practice of autopsy (dissection of cadavers) in Alexandria.
Whether Galen also studied anatomy this way is unclear. It is clear that Galen
(at least) engaged in comparative anatomy by dissecting monkeys.
In 157 Galen returned to his hometown to become a
surgeon to the gladiators. When civil unrest broke out in 162, Galen left for
Rome. The medical community in Rome was competitive and corrupt. In Rome,
Galen's ambition got the best of him with the result that his high profile
created powerful enemies who caused him to depart secretly in 166. After a
couple of years in obscurity, Galen was recalled by the Roman Emperors Marcus
Aurelius and Lucius Verus to serve the army in their war against the Germans. When
the plague hit Rome, Galen was made personal physician to Marcus Aurelius and
Aurelius' son, Commodus. For many years it has been held that Galen remained in
Roman society until his death around 199-200 (based upon the Suda Lexicon
written around 1000); however, new research by Vivian Nutton has persuasively
set the date of Galen's death much later. Nutton proposes that Galen may have
lived into his eighties (possibly as old as 87). The source for this new
information comes from Byzantine and Arab scholars from the sixth century
onwards. On the basis of this, it seems that Galen died around 216, give or take
several years, in the reign of Caracalla.
A great many of Galen's works have survived. The Kühn
edition of Galen (Greek with a Latin translation) runs over 20,000 pages. There
are other Galenic works that only exist in Arabic translations. However, many
of Galen's works are lost, e.g., many of his treatises on philosophy (logic,
physics, and ethics) perished in a fire that consumed the Temple of Peace in
191.
2. Hellenistic Schools of Medicine
During the end of the fourth century BCE and
throughout the third century BCE there were enormous advances in medicine
revolving around the principal practitioners: Diocles, Praxagoras, Herophilus,
and Erasistratus. During this period the debate about the relative roles of
theory and observation were central to these writers (Kühn X, 107). It is, in
fact, a perennial question in the philosophy of science. What is at issue is
when does one impose a theoretical structure on the world? Part of the answer
concerns the origins of the theoretical structure. From whence did it arise? In
part, this is a struggle for a logic of induction that might assist the
practitioner. Without such a theory of inductive logic, it is unclear whether
nature is revealing her nature to the careful observer or whether the observer
is imposing his own ideas upon nature. Aristotle discusses some of these
issues in Posterior Analytics II.19
and in The Parts of Animals I.
However, this is not the end of the question. Some of this tension can be seen
in the biomedical writers in the Hippocratic era. However, it is also
true that in the construction of scientific theories there must, of necessity,
be a tension between those who embrace theoretical structures and those who are
skeptical of them. The latter group generally bases their misgivings upon a
possible tendency among theorists to create an a priori science. What makes a priori science troublesome is that it breaks contact with
the empirical world. It suggests that ratiocination about natural causes is
sufficient for the production of scientific theories. For most natural
philosophers such a stance is entirely unacceptable. Setting the proper balance
between theory and observation was (and continues to me) an important question
in the philosophy of science.
One group that added to the debate on the role of
observation were the Empiricists. The origins of the Empiricist School might be
found in Acron of Akragas, a fifth century BCE follower of Empedocles. This conjecture
is based merely upon the testimony of later writers. It could certainly be the
case that there was no real medical empiricism, as such, before Serapion, a
third century BCE doctor .
Another interesting speculation on the origins of the
empiricist physicians comes from Michael Frede. Frede has suggested that from a
reference in Plato's Laws
720a-c; 857c-d that there was a two-tired medical system with physicians for
the wealthy (who employed theoretical principles) and physicians for the slaves
(who relied merely upon trial-and-error experience). If this speculation is
correct, then the burden of proof for the empiricists is to show that the
theoretical "book learning" of upper class doctors could be reduced
to mere experience. In other words, experience, itself, could generate
competence. The result would be an elevation of the second-level physician. If
Frede is correct on this, then perhaps social situation is partially
responsible for the rise of the medical empiricists.
Sextus Empiricus (circa 160-210)
set out a loosely woven doctrine of "consideration" or skepsis. Sextus is a key source of our
knowledge of Pyrrhonism and is also said to have been a physician (though his
writings on medicine have not survived). It is not clear whether Sextus was an
original thinker or merely a reflection of his era. However, at the very least,
one can garner background information of what might have influenced the
empiricists through the doctrine of skepsis.
Under this doctrine the theoretical structures of the philosophers
(Dogmatists) would be held in abeyance (neither accepted nor rejected). What
would rule the day would be the case before the physician right now. The case
and the physician's experience would dictate the treatment.
Against the Empiricists, on the other hand, were the
philosophers (Dogmatists). In one important way the Dogmatists are not a
"school" as such. They are often depicted by their detractors, such
as the Empiricists, rather than being self-identifying. This may relate to the
social class dynamics noted earlier. Thus, one should keep in mind that the
group is not so much a school of practitioners but a depiction of a group by
objectors to those who profess a foundation in medical theory. Perhaps the best
way to characterize the Dogmatists would be on the issue of aetiology. The
Empiricists attacked the Dogmatists for asserting that there might be hidden
causes of disease, and that these hidden causes might be grasped via
ratiocination. This was because (under this characterization) the Dogmatists
were advocating reasoning and conjecture over experience. To the Empiricists,
this was akin to creating a priori
science.
The Dogmatists (even in this quasi-class depiction)
were identified with one of the four prominent philosophical schools
(Platonists, Aristotelians/Peripatetics, Stoics, and Epicureans). Detractors
said that the Dogmatists honored theory over observation and experience. Of
course, from the point of view of the philosophical schools, rational theories
create a critical structure that aid in the interpretation and explanation of
nature. The sense of explanation here harkens back to Aristotle, who
distinguished knowing the fact (hoti) and
the reasoned fact (dioti, APo
II, i). It may not be enough to know that if I (as a physician) do x, then y
will result (anecdotal correlation of two events). That sort of hoti (or merely event + consequence unit)
is insufficient. The reason for this is that when circumstances alter slightly,
how is the practitioner to know whether this alteration is significant unless
he also has an appreciation of the mechanism that underlies the process? For
example, anecdotal correlation might (in a non-medical modern example) suggest
that every time I wash my car, it will rain. My personal experience may be
almost perfect, but that does not mean that such a causal connection actually
exists. The reluctance to embrace a non-observable causal mechanism leaves this
dilemma to those who profess an aversion to theory in favor of experience.
Somewhat in the middle of these two schools were the
Methodists. Aside from Soranus there are no surviving texts of the Methodists. Therefore
most of what we have comes from the descriptions of Galen and pseudo-Galen on
these writers. The following are cited as being Methodists: Thessalos, Themison,
Proklos, Reginos, Antipatros, Eudemos, Mnaseas, Philon, Dionysios, Menemachos,
Olympikos, Apollonides, Soranus, Julianus (Kühn X, 52-53, XIV, 684). There is
some controversy about the characterization and origins of this school but many
relate it to Themison of Laodicea a pupil of Asclepiades of Bithynia. However
this attribution is disputed by Celsus and Soranus who state that Themison is
not the first but merely a representative of Methodism. At any rate, the
Methodists paid attention (in contrast to the Dogmatists and Empiricists) to
the disease alone as opposed to the situation of the individual patient, that
is, his medical history and personal situation. The disease alone dictates
treatment (Kühn III, 14-20). Thus, the physician does not have to have
anatomical or physiological knowledge of the body. Instead, he observes the
body in a holistic manner (koinotetes). The
three principle conditions of a body viewed in this way are: (a) the body's
dryness, (b) the body's fluidity, and (c) the mixture of the two. The
"method" to be followed was to follow the phenomena. Underlying this
assumption was the notion about the status of pores in the mechanism of the
body's common balance. The body's pores allowed atoms to enter and exit the
body. When the atoms came and went freely health was the result. When there was
a disruption, then sickness was the result. When the pores were either too
small (constriction) or too large (dilatation) then an imbalance occurred in
the normal atomic flow. Atoms are invisible to the naked eye. Pores are
visible, but their subtle alterations are often not visibly detectable. Thus,
on the face of it, the Methodists seem to be contra-Empiricist. However, the
atomist tradition (upon which this theory rests) was taken to be Empiricist. (In
principle, one could view an
entirely physical event-if it were possible to witness it.) Thus, the
Methodists seem to have affinities to both. This is evident in Themison (first
century, BCE) and Thessalus (first century, AD). Disease was depicted as a
community of constriction or dilatation (or some combination of the two) that,
in principle, was observable even though, in practice, it couldn't be observed
except through its effects, namely, the disease. Thus, though the intent of the
Methodists was probably to lean toward the Empiricists, the actual practice put
them more in-between.
Galen often characterizes himself as an eclectic
belonging to no school. It is true that Galen was an innovator in observation,
for example he gave the first depiction of the four-chambered human heart. But
his epistemology was grounded in his philosophical training. Over and over
Galen relies on an over-arching medical theory to drive his aetiology (Kühn X,
123, 159, 246). In this way his practice is closest to Aristotelian critical
empiricism that requires careful observation and a comprehensive theory that
will make those observations meaningful.
3. Method
Because of Galen's pluralistic method, it is
appropriate that (for the most part) his own method draws upon his predecessors
with additions and corrections. For example, Galen employed the four-element
theory (earth, air, fire, and water) as well as the theories of the contraries
(hot, cold, wet, and dry). Though Aristotle interrelated these two
descriptive accounts in his work Generation
and Corruption, it is Galen who attempts to create a more gradated
form by making quasi-quantitative categories of the contraries to describe the
material composition of the mixtures (On
Mixtures). From the perspective of modern science, this is an
advancement upon Aristotle. This work on mixtures is
also used to account for the properties of drugs (On Simples). Drugs were supposed to counteract the
disposition of the body. Thus, if a patient were suffering from cold and wet
(upper respiratory infection), then the appropriate drug would be one that is
hot and dry (such as certain molds and fungi-does this remind you of
penicillin?). The use of broad-reaching natural principles enhanced the
explanatory power of Galen's theory of biological science.
Galen speaks at length about the philosophers Plato
(from whom he accepts the tri-partite soul) and Aristotle (whose biological
works are well known to him). In medicine, he is also greatly influenced by
historical figures such as Hippocrates (who he describes as a
single individual opposed to our modern understanding of a group of
writers-even though Galen was aware of the Hippocratic Question),
Herophilus, and especially Erasistratus. In his avowed work on biological
theory, On the Natural Faculties, Galen
goes to great lengths to refute the principles of Erasistratus and his
followers.
Contemporary figures are also discussed such as
Aclepiades, and the Methodists Themison and Thessalus. This thorough use of the
context of medicine allows Galen to consider, for example, Eristrates' theory
of mechanical digestion via a vacuum principle and to supplant it with his own
theory of attraction (holke). Galen's
theory of attraction may have had its roots in the theory of natural place that
always lacked a material force to implement it. At any rate, when the
mechanisms are inscrutable, it was important for Galen to offer an account that
fits into other parts of his theory (such as the mixture of the contraries in
the composition of the elements).
One of the most influential aspects of Galenic
practice was his implementation of (or invention of-as per Wesley Smith) the Hippocratic theory of the
four humours (phlegm, blood, black bile, and yellow bile). These points of
focus relate to a theory of health as balance. Each of these four humours is
related to the three principal points of the body: head (phlegm), heart
(blood), black bile (liver) and yellow bile (the liver's complement, the gall
bladder). The three principal points of the body are also loosely linked to the
Platonic tripartite soul: head (sophia, reason),
heart (thumos, emotion or
spiritedness), liver (epithumos, desire).
Thus, the sort of just balance of the soul that Plato argues for in the Republic is also the ground of natural
health. When one part of the soul/body is out of balance, then the individual
becomes ill. The physician's job is to assist the patient in maintaining
balance. If a person is too full of uncontrollable emotion or spiritedness, for
example, then he is suffering from too much blood. The obvious answer is to
engage in bloodletting (guaranteed to calm a person down). As in the case of
pharmacology and the contraries, the four humours provide a comprehensive
account of what it means to obtain and maintain health via the balancing of
various primary principles.
4. Galen's Critical Empiricism
One of the striking features of ancient medicine is
the extent that very limited observations had to be interpreted in order to
explain natural function. For example, given that blood was considered to be
nourishment, trophe, it seemed
reasonable (following Aristotle) that the blood would be
entirely consumed by the body's tissue. Thus, the blood would be manufactured
in the liver and heart and then would flow to the rest of the body and be
consumed. The flow of blood went one-way. However, there was a problem: there
were two sorts of blood vessels (veins and arteries). These were structurally
distinct. This was known through dissection of primates. Then it is assumed
that Nature does nothing in vain (discussed at length in On the Use of the Parts as a key
biomedical explanatory principle). This means that the veins and arteries have
different functions. But they cannot be too disparate. The answer to this
dilemma for Galen is that the arteries carry blood mixed with aer or pneuma
that acts as a vital force whereas the venous blood is ordinary-though Galen
held (correctly) that the two systems were connected by tiny almost invisible
vessels (capillaries).
Thus Galen began with a problem and a number of
observations and sought to make sense of the seeming anomalies via his
overarching biomedical principles. In this way, Galen was acting according to
the mathematical training from his father and a desire to create a unified
(quasi-axiomatic) explanatory system. Without observation, this could have led
to a priori or
"armchair" science. But when combined with careful observation, it
leads to critical empiricism.
Another example of this mixture of observation and
inference is in the area of conception theory. Galen says in his treatise, On Seed,
These things have been said by me because of some of
the philosophers who call themselves Aristotelians and Peripatetics. I, at
least, would not address these men so, they being so greatly ignorant of the
opinion of Aristotle that they think it is
pleasing to him that the sperm of the male being cast into the uterus of the female
places the principle of motion in the katamenia
(the female seed) and, after this is expelled, the principle of
motion in the katamenia and,
after it is expelled, does not any part become the corporeal substance of the
fetus. They have been deceived by the first book of the Generation of Animals that alone of the
five they seem to have read. These things are written there, "As we said,
of the generation of the principles we may say that chiefly there are the male
principle and the female principle. The male offers the motive principle and
the efficient cause of generation while the female offers the material
principle" [Galen quoting Aristotle, G.A. 716a 5].
These are not far after the beginning: in still later
parts of the tract he writes as well, "But this may be well concluded that
the male provides the form and the principle of motion and the female provides
the body and the matter just as the example of curding milk. Here the body is
the milk and the fig juice contains the principle that makes it
curdle" [Galen quoting Aristotle, G.A. 729a 10; Kühn IV,
516-517, my tr.].
The biological accounts of human reproduction in the
ancient world offer excellent examples of the interaction between observation
and inference. There are a number of issues involved in this issue that
pre-dates even the Hippocratic writers. The one that is
mentioned here is the issue of whether there is one seed (the male's only) or
two (the male's and the female's). In the above example Galen seems to be
saying that the first reading of Aristotle in which the male provides
the efficient cause and the female provides the material cause, simpliciter, is a misreading of Aristotle. Instead,
the event (conception) is depicted as a more involved process in which
principles of both parents come into play. These principles revolve around the
empirically observable facts that children as often as not resemble the mother
as much as the father. The "one seed" theory in which the father's
seed, alone, fashions the child can only account for such an outcome by calling
it a sort of mutation (agone, para physin).
But regularity counts for something. It is odd when an event that
may approach or exceed 50% is called a mutation. This turns the entire idea of
mutation (a statistical anomaly) on its head.
Galen approaches the issue with a balanced approach
beginning with anatomical observations. Galen did some of the most extensive
work in the ancient world on the study of the female anatomy (albeit mostly
upon apes, On Anatomical Procedures, I.2).
Galen's observation of a fluid in the horns of the uterus (Kühn IV, 594,
600-601) were the basis of his (mistaken) view that he had discovered female
seed. However, in the midst of this mistake he was on the right track in
viewing the ovaries as analogous to the male testes.
The point in this second example is that Galen wanted
to combine his observations gained in dissections of apes to his pronouncements
vis-à-vis the debate concerning "one seed conception" vs. "two
seed conception." This commitment to integrating observation and theory
contributed to making Galen a towering figure in medicine and the philosophy of
science.
5. Select Bibliography
Primary Texts
- Galeni Opera Omnia. Basel: Par'Andrea to Kratandro, 1538.Kühn, C.G. Galeni Opera Omnia. Leipzig: C. Cnobloch, 1821-1833, rpt. Hildesheim, 1965.
- This is still the standard edition though it is very gradually being supplanted by the Corpus Medicorum Graecorum Leipzig, 1914-present.
Key Texts in Translation
- Abhandlung darüber, dass der vorzügliche Arzt Philosoph sein muss. [Quod optimus medicus sit idem philosophus] translated by Peter Bachmann. Göttingen: Vanderhoeck & Ruprecht, 1996.L'Áme et ses passions: Les passions et les erreurs de l'áme. Translated and notes by Vincent Barras. Paris: Les Belle Lettres, 1995.
- Galen on Antecedent Causes. Edited and translated with introduction and commentary by R.J. Hankinson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- Galen on Bloodletting. Translated by Peter Brain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.
- Galen on Food and Diet. Translated and notes by Mark Grant. London: Routledge, 2000.
- Galen's Institutio logica. Translated with commentary by John Spangler Kieffer. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1964.
- Galen on Language and Ambiguity (De captionibus). Translated with commentary by Robert Blair Edlow. Leiden: Brill, 1977.
- Galen on the Natural Faculties. Translated by Arthur John Brock. London: Heineiman, Ltd., 1952. Loeb series.
- Galen on the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body {De usu partium). Translated with commentary by Margaret Tallmadge May. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1968.
- Galen, The Therapeutic Method: Books 1 & 2 (De methodo medendi). Edited and translated by R.J. Hankinson. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991.
Selected Secondary Sources
- Barnes, Jonathan. "A Third Sort of Syllogism: Galen and the Logic of Relations" in Modern Thinkers and Ancient Thinkers. R. W. Sharples, ed. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993.Boylan, Michael. "Galen's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 19.1 (1986): 44-77.
- Boudon-Millot, ed, fr. tr. Introduction génerale; sur ses propres livres que l’excellent médecin devienne philosophe. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2007.
- Boudon-Millot, And Alessia Guardasole, and Caroline Magdelaine, eds. La science médicale antique: nouveaux regards: etudes reunites en l’honneur de Jacques Jouanna. Paris: Beauchesne, 2007.
- Boylan, Michael. “Galen on the Blood, Pulse, and Arteries” Journal of the History of Biology 40.2 (2007): 207-230.
- Boylan, Michael. "The Hippocratic and Galenic Challenges to Aristotle's Conception Theory" Journal of the History of Biology 15.1 (1984): 83-112.
- Connell, Sophia. "Aristotle and Galen on Sex Difference and Reproduction: A New Approach to an Ancient Rivalry." Studies in History and the Philosophy of Science. 31-a.3(2000):405-427.
- Cosans, Christopher E. "The Experimental Foundations of Galen's Teleology" Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 29A.1 (1998): 63-90.
- Crombie, A. C. Augustine to Galileo. Vol. 1. London: Heinemann, 1961.
- DeLacy, Philip. "Galen's Platonism" American Journal of Philology. 93 (1972): 27-39.
- Durling, Richard. A Dictionary of Medical Terms. Leiden: Brill, 1993.
- Edelstein, Ludwig. Ancient Medicine. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967.
- Farrington, B. Greek Science: Theophrastus to Galen. Baltimore, MD: Penguin, 1953.
- Fischer, Klaus-Dietrich ed., Text and Tradition: Studies in Ancient Greek Medicine and its Transmission: Presented to Jutta Kollesch Leiden: Brill, 1998.
- Frede, Michael. "The Empiricist Attitude toward Reason and Theory" Apeiron. 21 (1988): 79-97.
- Freudiger, Jurg. "Methodus resolutiva: Antikes und Neuzeitliches in Jacopo Acontios Methodenschrift" Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie. 45.3 (1998): 407-446.
- Gill, Christopher. "Galen vs. Chrysippus on the Tripartite Psyche in 'Timaeus' 69-72" in Interpreting the 'Timaeus-Critias. Tomas Calvo ed. Sankt Augustin: Academia: 1997.
- Gill, Christopher. "Did Chrysippus Understand Medea?" Phronesis. 28.2 (1983): 136-149.
- Hankinson, R. J. "Actions and Passions" in Passions and Perceptions. Martha Nussbaum, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
- Hankinson, R.J. The Cambridge Companion to Galen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
- Hankinson, R. J. "Galen's Anatomy of the Soul" Phronesis 36.3 (1991): 197-233.
- Hankinson, R. J. "A Purely Verbal Dispute? Galen on Stoic and Academic Epistemology" Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 45.178 (1991): 267-300.
- Hankinson, R. J. "Evidence, Externality and Antecendence: Inquiries Into Later Greek Causal Concepts." Phronesis 32.1 (1987): 80-100.
- Hankinson, R. J. "Causes and Empiricism: A Problem in the Interpretation of Later Greek Medical Method." Phronesis 32.4 (1987): 329-348.
- Kagan, Jerome, Nancy Snidman, Doreen Ardus, J. Steven Rezinck. Galen's Prophecy: Temperament in Human Nature. NY: Basic Books, 1994.
- Kember, O. "Right and Left in the Sexual Theories of Parmenides" Journal of Hellenic Studies. 91 (1971): 70-79.
- Kidd, I. G. "Posidonius on Emotions" in Problems in Stoicism. A. A. Long, ed. London: Athlone, 1971.
- Kollesch, Jutta. Galen über das Riechorgan. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1964.
- Kollesch, Jutta and Diethard Nickel, eds. Galen und das hellenistische Erbe. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner, 1993.
- Kudlien, Fridolf and Richard J. Durling. Galen's Method of Healing. Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1991.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. Greek Science After Aristotle. New York: Norton, 1973.
- Lloyd, G.E.R. "Parmenides' Sexual Theories: A Reply to MER Kember" Journal of Hellenic Studies. 92 (1972): 178-179.
- Lumpe, Adolf. "Der logische Grundgedanke der vierten Schlussfigur." Prima Philosophia. 11.4 (1998): 397-404.
- Lumpe, Adolf. "Zur Anordnung der Pramissen des kategorischen Syllogismus bei Albinos, Galenus und Pseudo-Apuleius" Prima Philosophia 8.2 (1995): 115-124.
- Mansfield, Jaap. "The Idea of the Will in Chrysippus, Posidonius, and Galen" Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 7 (1991): 107-145.
- Manuli, Paola. "Galien et le Stoicisme" Revue de Mataphysique et de Morale 97.3 (1992): 365-375.
- Mowry, Bryan. "From Galen's Theory to William Harvey's Theory: A Case Study in the Rationality of Scientific Theory Change" Studies in History and the Philosophy of Science 16 (1985): 49-82.
- Nutton, Vivian. Ancient Medicine. London: Routledge, 2004.
- Nutton, Vivian. "The Chronology of Galen's Early Career" Classical Quarterly 23 (1973): 158-171.
- Nutton, Vivian. (ed.) Galen: Problems and Prospects. London: Wellcome Institute, 1981.
- Nutton, Vivian. "Galen ad multos annos" Dynamis 15 (1995): 25-39.
- Rescher, Nicholas. Galen and the Syllogism: An Examination of the Thesis that Galen Originated the Fourth Figure of the Syllogism in Light of New Data from the Arabic. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1996.
- Sarton, George. Galen of Pergamon. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press, 1954.
- Siegel, Rudolph. Galen's System of Physiology and Medicine. Basel: Karger, 1968.
- Smith, Wesley. The Hippocratic Tradition. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979.
- Temkin, Owsei. Galenism: The Rise and Decline of a Medical Philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1973.
- Tieleman, Teun. "Plotinus on the Seat of the Soul: Reverberations of Galen and Alexander in Enn. IV, 3 27ESS, 23." Phronesis. 43.4 (1998): 306-325.
Select Proceedings of Conferences on Galen
1981 English
- Nutton, Vivian, Galen : Problems and Prospects. London: Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, 1981.
1982 English
- Kudlien, F., & Durling, R. J. Galen's method of healing : Proceedings of the 1982 Galen Symposium. Paper presented at the Galen Symposium (1982 : Christian-Albrechts Universität); Studies in Ancient Medicine,; v. 1, 205. Leiden: Brill, 1991.
1986 3rd Italian
- Manuli, P., & Vegretti, M. (1988). Le Opere Psicologiche di Galeno : Atti del terzo Colloquio Galenico Internazionale, Pavia, 10-12 Settembre 1986. Paper presented at the Colloqio Galenico Internazionale (3d : 1986 : Pavia, Italy); Elenchos (Bibliopolis (Firm)) 13,
1989 4th German
- Kollesch, J., Nickel, D., Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, & Institut für Geschichte der Medizin. (1993). Galen und das Hellenistische Erbe : Verhandlungen des IV. Internationalen Galen-Symposiums veranstaltet vom Institut für Geschichte der Medizin am Bereich Medizin (charité) der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin 18.-20. September 1989. Paper presented at the Galen Symposium (4th : 1989 : Humboldt-Universität Zu Berlin); Sudhoffs Archiv.; Beihefte,; Heft 32,
1995 5th English
- Debru, A. (1997). Galen on Pharmacology : Philosophy, history, and medicine : Proceedings of the Vth International Galen Colloquium, Lille, 16-18 March 1995. Paper presented at the International Galen Colloquium (5th : 1995 : Lille, France); Studies in Ancient Medicine,; v. 16, 336. Leiden: Brill, 2007.
1988 Spanish
- López Férez, J. A. (1991). Galeno, obra, pensamiento e influencia : Coloquio internacional celebrado en Madrid, 22-25 de marzo de 1988. Madrid : Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia, 1991.
2002 Italian
- Garofalo, I., Roselli, A., Fischer, K., Galen, On the therapeutic method, & Book III. (2003). Galenismo e Medicina Tardoantica : Fonti greche, latine e arabe : Atti del Seminario Internazionale di Siena, Certosa di Pontignano, 9 e 10 Settembre 2002. Paper presented at the Annali Dell'Istituto Universitario Orientale Di Napoli.; Sezione Filologico-Letteraria.; Quaderni,; 7,
2002 English
- Nutton, Vivian. The Unknown Galen. London : Institute of Classical Studies, School of Advanced Study, University of London, 2002.
Author Information
GALENO (131 - 201)
Cláudio Galeno ou Élio Galeno
(lat. Claudius Galenus e Gr. Κλαύδιος Γαληνός, Pérgamo, c. 129 -
provavelmente Sicília, c. 217), mais conhecido como Galeno de Pérgamo
foi um proeminente médico e filósofo romano
de origem grega,[1] e provavelmente o
mais talentoso médico investigativo do período romano. Suas teorias dominaram e
influenciaram a ciência médica ocidental por mais de um milênio. Seus relatos
de anatomia médica eram
baseados em macacos, visto que a dissecação humana não era permitida no seu
tempo [2] , mas foram
insuperáveis até a descrição impressa e ilustrações de dissecções humanas por Andreas
Vesalius em 1543.[3] . Desta forma
Galeno é também um precursor da prática da vivissecção (dissecação em animais vivos) e experimentação
com animais.
Contribuições na Medicina
A
maioria de suas obras e seus estudos se perderam. Sabe-se, contudo, que Galeno
investigou anatomia, fisiologia, patologia,
sintomatologia e terapêutica. Foi o mais destacado médico de seu tempo e
o 1.º que conduziu pesquisas fisiológicas.
Fez
muitas importantes descobertas, como distinguir as veias das artérias, o sangue
venoso do arterial, propor pela 1.ª vez que o corpo fosse controlado pelo
Cérebro, dando a distinção entre nervos sensoriais e motores, descobrindo que
os rins processam a urina e demonstrando que a laringe é responsável pela voz.[4]. A descrição feita por
Galeno das atividades do coração, artérias e veias durou até que William Harvey estabelecesse que
o sangue circula com o coração agindo como uma bomba em 1628.[5] No séc. 19, os
estudantes de medicina ainda liam Galeno para aprender alguns conceitos. Ele
desenvolveu muitas experiências com ligações nervosas que apoiaram a teoria,
ainda aceita hoje, de que o cérebro controla
todos os movimentos dos músculos por
meio do crânio e do sistema
nervoso periférico.[6]
Por
volta de 170, realizou uma experiência que iria mudar o curso da medicina:
demonstrou pela 1.ª vez que as artérias conduzem sangue e não ar, como até então se acreditava. No campo da anatomia, Galeno distinguiu ainda
os ossos com e sem cavidade medular.
Descreveu a caixa craniana e o sistema muscular. Pesquisou os nervos do crânio e reconheceu os
raquidianos, os cervicais, os recorrentes e uma parte do sistema
simpático. Também foi o 1.º a demonstrar (baseado em experiências)
que o rim é um órgão excretor de urina. Farmacologia
também interessava Galeno.
Foi
um conhecido cirurgião e muitos dos seus procedimentos e técnicas ousados
demais para seu tempo só seriam usadas novamente séculos depois, como por ex.
sua intervenção cirurgica para correção da catarata.[7]
Em
vista das limitações técnicas (em especial limitações ópticas), Galeno
inevitavelmente acabou cometendo erros. Não era possível ver o que se passava
no interior dos órgãos. Seus 2 maiores erros ocorreram em sua teoria da
circulação e na sua idéia de que cada órgão realiza sua função própria devido a
uma ação de forças que atuavam sobre os órgãos. Segundo ele, o sangue circulava devido ao
impulso ou força atrativa cuja origem era a própria parede da artéria. Tal
concepção foi estendida para todos os órgãos. O respeito pelas suas teorias era
tão grande que levou mais de 15 séculos para que sua teoria das forças fosse
contestada (já que os médicos consideravam suas teorias infalíveis). Foi graças
à difusão da medicina árabe e ao médico inglês William Harvey que os erros de
Galeno neste assunto foram corrigidos.
Contribuições na Filosofia
Galeno
escreveu uma pequena obra chamada "O
Melhor Médico é Também um Filósofo",[8] e ele via a si próprio
como sendo ambos, o que significava embasar a prática médica no aparente
conhecimento teórico ou "filosofia", como era chamado em seu tempo. Ele
estava muito interessado na disputa entre as facções médicas racionalistas e
empiristas,[9] e sua utilização da
observação direta, dissecação e vivissecção na formação médica e
como forma de fundamentar a prática médica pode ser entendida como tendo
considerado ambas as perspectivas e construído um fundamento mais complexo e
mesclado que evitou problemas com cada posição.[10]
Biografia
Ele
descreve seus 1.ºs anos de vida em "Sobre as moléstias da mente".
Nascido em setembro de 129 d.C.,[1] seu pai Élio
Nicon foi um rico patrício, arquiteto e construtor
com interesses ecléticos, incluindo filosofia, matemática, lógica, astronomia,
agricultura e literatura. Descreve seu pai como um "homem muito afável,
justo, bom e benevolente". Naquela época Pérgamo era um grande centro
cultural e intelectual, notável por sua biblioteca (expandida por Eumenes II), só inferior à de
Alexandria[11] [12] e atraía tanto
filósofos estoicos como platônicos, a quem Galeno foi
apresentado aos 14 anos. Seus estudos também abrangeram cada um dos principais
sistemas filosóficos da época, incluindo o aristotélico e o epicurista. Seu pai tinha lhe planejado
uma carreira tradicional na filosofia ou na política e teve o cuidado de
expô-lo a influências literárias e filosóficas. No entanto Galeno afirma que
por volta de 145 seu pai teve um sonho em que deus Esculápio apareceu e ordenou a
Nicon que seu filho estudasse medicina. Novamente, nenhuma despesa foi poupada
e após sua inicial educação liberal, aos 16 começou a estudar no prestigiado
santuário local ou Asclepeion,
dedicado a Esculápio, o deus da medicina, como um θεραπευτής (auxiliar
para tratamento ou atendente) por 4 anos. Lá, sofreu influências de homens como
Aeschrion de Pérgamo, Stratonicus e Sátiro. Esses santuários
funcionavam como spas ou sanatórios onde o doente vinha procurar ajuda do
sacerdócio. O templo de Pérgamo era procurado avidamente pelos romanos em busca
de uma cura. Foi também o refúgio de pessoas notáveis como Cláudio Charax, o
historiador, Aélio Aristeides, o orador, Polemo,
o sofista, e Cáspio Rufino, o cônsul.[1]
Galeno
iniciou seus estudos em filosofia e
medicina por volta de 146 d.C. em
Pérgamo, sua cidade natal. Após dois anos, achou que nada mais tinha a aprender
e partiu para outros centros como Esmirna, Corinto e Alexandria a fim de se
aperfeiçoar. Voltou para Pérgamo em 157, julgando terminada sua instrução.
Passou, então, a ocupar o cargo de médico da escola de gladiadores,
especializando-se em cirurgia e dietética.
Sendo
Roma o centro do mundo àquela época, Galeno partiu para aquela cidade em 162.
Galeno, que já havia ganho fama ao curar um milionário de nome Eudemo, torna-se
ainda mais famoso. Tão famoso que se tornou médico particular do imperador
romano Marco Aurélio.
Suas conferências sobre medicina e higiene eram tão concorridas que ele
as apresentava em um teatro. As aulas práticas que conduzia contemplavam vivissecção e necropsia. Permaneceu em Roma até
192, se afastando da cidade apenas por um curto período em que esteve no Oriente
Médio. Ao fim da vida, retornou para Pérgamo.
Obras
Entre suas obras destacam-se (?):
- Comentários a Hipócrates
- Sobre as seitas
- Sobre a melhor doutrina
- Sobre a medicina empírica
- De anatomicis administrationibus (em quinze volumes)
- De usu partium corporis humani
- Método terapêutico
Obra – Sobre as Faculdades Naturais
Se o trabalho de Hipócrates é tomado como
representando a fundação da antiga medicina grega, então o trabalho de Galeno,
que viveu cerca de 600 anos depois, pode ser considerado como o ápice do mesmo
edifício.
Ele nasceu em Pérgamo, em 129, e lá e em outros
centros acadêmicos do Egeu prosseguiu seus estudos médicos antes de ser nomeado
médico para os gladiadores de Pérgamo em 157. Tornando-se insatisfeito com esse
tipo de prática, ele emigrou para Roma, onde logo ganhou reconhecimento da
autoridade médica mais importante de seu tempo e onde, com uma breve
interrupção, ele permaneceu até sua morte em 199.
O mérito de Galeno é ter se cristalizado ou levado
ao foco do melhor trabalho das escolas médicas gregas que precederam seu
próprio tempo. É essencialmente na forma de galenismo que a medicina grega foi
transmitida após séculos.
Referências
·
Nutton,
Vivian. 1973. "The Chronology of Galen's Early Career". Classical
Quarterly 23:158-171.
·
Arthur
Aufderheide, 'The Scientific Study of Mummies' (2003), página 5
·
O'Malley, C.,
Andreas Vesalius of Brussels, 1514-1564, Berkeley: University of
California Press
·
Galen on anatomical procedures: De
anatomicis administrationibus, de Claudii Galeni Pergameni, traduzido por Charles Joseph Singer
·
Furley, D,
and J. Wilkie, 1984, Galen On Respiration and the Arteries, Princeton
University Press, and Bylebyl, J (ed), 1979, William Harvey and His Age,
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
·
Frampton, M.,
2008, Embodiments of Will: Anatomical and Physiological Theories of
Voluntary Animal Motion from Greek Antiquity to the Latin Middle Ages, 400
B.C.–A.D. 1300, Saarbrücken: VDM Verlag. pp. 180 - 323
·
Brian, P.,
1979, "Galen on the ideal of the physician", South Africa Medical
Journal, 52: 936-938
·
Frede, M. and
R. Walzer, 1985, Three Treatises on the Nature of Science, Indianapolis:
Hacket.
·
De Lacy, P.,
1972, "Galen's Platonism", American Journal of Philosophy, pp.
27-39, Cosans, C., 1997, “Galen’s Critique of Rationalist and Empiricist
Anatomy”, Journal of the History of Biology, 30: 35-54, and Cosans, C.,
1998, “The Experimental Foundations of Galen’s Teleology”, Studies in
History and Philosophy of Science, 29: 63-80.
·
Brock AJ.
Introduction. Galen. On the Natural Faculties. Edinburgh
1916
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário