ANAXÁGORAS (500 - 428 a.C.)
It was an early Pre-Socratic Greek philosopher from Ionia,
although he was one of the first philosophers to move to Athens as a base. He is sometimes considered
to be part of the poorly-defined school
of Pluralism, and
some of his ideas also influenced the later development of Atomism. Many of
his ideas in the physical sciences were quite revolutionary in their
day, and quite insightful in retrospect.
Life
Anaxagoras (pronounced an-ax-AG-or-as) was born around
500 B.C. to an aristocratic and landed family in the city of Clazomenae
(or Klazomenai) in the Greek colony of Ionia (on the west coast
of present-day Turkey).
As a young man, he became the first of the major Pre-Socratic philosophers to move to Athens (which was then rapidly
becoming the centre of Greek culture), where he remained for about
thirty years.
During this time he became a favourite (and
possibly a teacher) of the prominent and influential statesman, orator
and general Pericles (c. 495 – 429 B.C.), one of the architects of Athens' primacy during the
Golden Age. Although it seems that Anaxagoras and the young Socrates never actually met, one of Socrates' teachers, Archelaus, studied under Anaxagoras
for some time. His work was also known to the major writers of the day,
including Sophocles, Euripides, Aeschylus and Aristophanes.
In about 450 B.C., however, Anaxagoras was arrested
by Pericles' political opponents on a charge of contravening the established
religion by his teachings on origins of the universe, the first philosopher
before Socrates to be brought to trial for impiety. With
Pericles' influence he was released, but he was forced to retire from Athens to exile in Lampsacus in Ionia, where he died around the year 428 B.C.
Work
Anaxagoras wrote at least one book of
philosophy, but only fragments of the first part of this have survived
in work of Simplicius of Cilicia in the 6th Century A.D.
He is best known for his cosmological theory of
the origins and structure of the universe. He maintained that the original
state of the cosmos was a thorough mixture of all its ingredients,
although this mixture was not entirely uniform, and some ingredients are
present in higher concentrations than others and varied from place to
place. At some point in time, this primordial mixture was set in motion by the
action of nous ("mind"), and the whirling motion shifted and separated
out the ingredients, ultimately producing the cosmos of separate material
objects (with differential properties) that we perceive today.
For Anaxagoras, this was a purely mechanistic
and naturalistic process, with no need for gods or any
theological repercussions. However, he did not elucidate on the precise nature
of Mind, which he appears to consider material, but distinguished from the
rest of matter in that it is finer, purer and able to act freely. It is also present
in some way in everything, a kind of Dualism.
Anaxagoras developed his metaphysical theories from his cosmological theory. He accepted
the ideas of Parmenides and the Eleatics that the senses cannot be trusted and that any apparent
change is merely a rearrangement of the unchanging, timeless
and indestructible ingredients of the universe. Not only then is it impossible
for things to come into being (or to cease to be), he also held that there is a
share of everything in everything, and that the original ingredients of
the cosmos are effectively omnipresent (e.g. he argued that the food an
animal eats turns into bone, hair, flesh, etc, so it must already
contain all of those constituents within it). He denied that there is any
limit to the smallness or largeness of the particles of the
original cosmic ingredients, so that infinitesimally small fragments of all
other ingredients can still be present within an object which appears to
consist entirely of just one material (presaging to some extent the ideas of Atomism).
In the physical sciences, Anaxagoras was the
first to give the correct explanation of eclipses, and was both famous
and notorious for his scientific theories, including his claims that the
sun is a mass of red-hot metal, that the moon is earthy, and that
the stars are fiery stones.
Anaxagoras (c. 500—428 B.C.E.)
Anaxagoras of Clazomenae was an important Presocratic natural
philosopher and scientist who lived and taught in Athens for approximately thirty years. He
gained notoriety for his materialistic views, particularly his contention that
the sun was a fiery rock. This led to charges of impiety, and he was sentenced
to death by the Athenian court. He avoided this penalty by leaving Athens, and he spent his
remaining years in exile. While Anaxagoras proposed theories on a variety of
subjects, he is most noted for two theories. First, he speculated that in the
physical world everything contains a portion of everything else. His
observation of how nutrition works in animals led him to conclude that in order
for the food an animal eats to turn into bone, hair, flesh, and so forth, it must
already contain all of those constituents within it. The second theory of
significance is Anaxagoras’ postulation of Mind (Nous) as the initiating and governing principle of the
cosmos.
1. Life and Writing
The exact chronology of Anaxagoras is unknown, but most accounts place
his dates around 500-428 BCE. Some have argued for dates of c. 534-467 BCE, but
the 500-428 time period is the most commonly accepted among scholars.
Anaxagoras was born in Ionia in the town of Clazomenae,
a lively port city on the coast of present-day Turkey. As such, he is considered
to be both the geographical and theoretical successor to the earliest Ionian
philosophers, particularly Anaximenes. Eventually, Anaxagoras made his way to Athens and he is often
credited with making her the home of Western philosophical and physical
speculation. Anaxagoras remained in Athens
for some thirty years, according to most accounts, until he was indicted on the
charge of impiety and sentenced to death. Rather than endure this penalty,
Anaxagoras, with the help of his close friend and student, Pericles, went to
Lampsacus, in Asia Minor, where he lived until
his death.
Anaxagoras’ trial and sentencing in Athens were motivated by a combination of
political and religious concerns. His close association with Pericles left him
vulnerable to those who wished to discredit the powerful and controversial
student through the teacher. Furthermore, his materialistic beliefs and
teachings were quite contrary to the standard orthodoxy of the time,
particularly his view that the heavenly bodies were fiery masses of rock
whirling around the earth in ether. Such convictions are famously attested to
inPlato’s Apology when Socrates, accused by Meletus
of believing that the sun is stone and the moon is earth, distances himself
from such atheistic notions:
My dear Meletus, do you think you are prosecuting Anaxagoras? Are you so
contemptuous of the jury and think them so ignorant of letters as not to know
that the books of Anaxagoras of Clazomenae are full of those theories, and
further, that the young men learn from me what they can buy from time to time
for a drachma, at most, in the bookshops, and ridicule Socrates if he pretends
that these theories are his own, especially as they are so absurd? (26d)
As with the dates of his birth and death, the chronology of Anaxagoras’
exile and subsequent time in Lampsacus are a bit of a mystery. Some of the
historical testimonies indicate that his trial occurred shortly before the
Peloponnesian War, around 431 BCE. If this is the case, then Anaxagoras’ time
in exile would have lasted no more than a few years. Other records indicate
that his trial and exile occurred much earlier, and his time in Lampsacus
enabled him to start an influential school where he taught for nearly twenty
years. With regard to the persona of Anaxagoras, there are quite a few
interesting anecdotes that paint a picture of an ivory tower scientist and
philosopher who was extremely detached from the general concerns and practical
matters of life. While the stories are possibly fanciful, the consistent image
of Anaxagoras presented throughout antiquity is that of a person entirely
consumed by the pursuit of knowledge. In fact, he apparently maintained that
the opportunity to study the universe was the fundamental reason why it is
better to be born than to not exist.
In his Lives of the
Philosophers, Diogenes Laertius states that Anaxagoras is among those philosophers
who wrote only one book. This work was a treatise on natural philosophy and, as
the above quote from the Apology
indicates, it was probably not a very long work, since it could be purchased
for “a drachma, at most.” Although the book has not survived, it was available
until at least the sixth-century CE. While it is impossible to recreate the
entire content and order of his work, various ancient sources have provided
scholars with enough information to fairly represent Anaxagoras’ philosophy.
Noteworthy among these sources are Aristotle, Theophrastus (ca. 372-288 BCE) and Themistius (ca. 317-387 CE). We
are primarily indebted, however, to Simplicius (sixth-century CE) for most of
our knowledge of, and access to, the fragments of Anaxagoras’ work. Before
moving on to the theories of Anaxagoras, it should be noted that there are some
rather wide ranging disagreements among scholars today about some of the basic
tenets of his philosophy. In fact, within the past twenty years or so, there
have been a greater variety of interpretations of Anaxagoras than perhaps any
other Presocratic philosopher.
2. The Structure of Things: A Portion of Everything in Everything
Anaxagoras’ innovative theory of physical nature is encapsulated in the
phrase, “a portion of everything in everything.” Its primary expression is
found in the following difficult fragment:
And since the portions of both the large and the small are equal in
amount, in this way too all things would be in everything; nor can they be
separate, but all things have a portion of everything. Since there cannot be a
smallest, nothing can be separated or come to be by itself, but as in the
beginning now too all things are together. But in all things there are many
things, equal in amount, both in the larger and the smaller of the things being
separated off. (frag. 6)
It should be pointed out that it is rather difficult to determine what
exactly Anaxagoras meant by “things.” It is tempting to view this as a theory
of matter, but this would be misguided as it tends to apply later Aristotelian
categories and interpretations onto Anaxagoras. At times, the term “seeds” has
been utilized but it would seem that many scholars today prefer the neutral
term “stuffs” to depict this notion. In any case, this rather complex theory is
best understood as Anaxagoras’ attempt to reconcile his perceptions of the
world with an influential argument (presented some time earlier by Parmenides) about how reality
must be conceived.
a. The Challenge of Parmenides
According to Parmenides, whatever is, is (being) and whatever is not, is
not (nonbeing). As a result, whatever constitutes the nature of reality must
always “have been” since nothing can come into being from nothing. Furthermore,
reality must always “be” since being (what is) cannot become nonbeing (what is
not). This argument led Parmenides to a monistic and static conception of
reality. As such, the world of changing particulars is deceptive, despite
appearances to the contrary. Anaxagoras appears to accept this argument of
Parmenides as the following statement indicates: “The Greeks are wrong to
accept coming to be and perishing, for no thing comes to be, nor does it
perish.” (frag. 17) Anaxagoras could not, however, square the thesis of radical
monism with his experience of a world that seems to admit plurality and change.
In fact, if all of the theses of Parmenides are correct, there is no
possibility of science because all empirically gathered data is misleading.
Therefore, the challenge for Anaxagoras and other post-Parmenidian philosophers
was to present a proper account of nature while maintaining the demand that the
stuff that constitutes reality can neither come into being from nothing nor
pass away into nonbeing.
b. Empedocles’s Theory
Empedocles was a contemporary
of Anaxagoras and, while the historical records are inconclusive, it is
possible that the latter was partially reacting to the theory of the former in
the development of his own views. In response to Parmenides, Empedocles
maintained that the four elements—earth, air, fire, water—were the constituents
or “roots” of all matter. These four roots cannot come into being, be destroyed
or admit any change. Therefore, apart from the fact that there are four, they
are essentially identical to the “one” of Parmenides. The roots mix together in
various proportions to account for all the things in the world that we suppose
to be real, such as apples, horses, etc. As an apple dissolves, it does not
collapse into nonbeing, rather the mixture that has accounted for the apparent
apple of our senses has simply been rearranged. Apples, and other “mortal
things,” as Empedocles called them, do not actually come to be, nor are they
actually destroyed. This is simply the way humans like to talk about entities
which appear to exist but do not.
Anaxagoras’ relationship to Empedocles is difficult to discern, but it
is possible that he was not satisfied with Empedocles’ response to Parmenides
and the Eliatics. On Aristotle’s interpretation, Anaxagoras maintained that the
pluralism of Empedocles unduly singled out certain substances as primary and
others as secondary. According to Anaxagoras, the testimony of our senses
maintains that hair or flesh exist as assuredly as earth, air, water or fire.
In fact, all of the infinite numbers of substances are as real as the root substances.
Therefore, under this interpretation the key problem for Anaxagoras is that
under Empodocles' theory it would be possible to divide a hair into smaller and
smaller pieces until it was no longer hair, but a composite of the root
substances. As such, this would no longer satisfy the requirement that a
definite substance cannot pass into nonbeing. According to other
interpretations, however, some of the textual evidence from Anaxagoras seems to
suggest that he treated some “things” (ala Empedocles) as more basic and
primary than others. In any case, the theoretical distinctions between the two
philosophers are somewhat unclear. Despite these difficulties, it is clear that
Anaxagoras proposes a theory of things that is distinct from Empedocles while
encountering the challenges of Parmenides.
c. The Lesson of Nutrition
While there is some recent scholarly debate about this, Anaxagoras’
contention that all things have a portion of everything may have had its
genesis in the phenomenon of nutrition. He observed among animals that the food
that is used to nourish develops into flesh, hair, etc. For this to be the
case, Anaxagoras believed that rice, for instance, must contain within it the
substances hair and flesh. Again, this is in keeping with the notion that
definite substances cannot arise from nothing: “For how can hair come to be
from not hair or flesh from not flesh?” (frag. 10). Moreover, not only does a
piece of rice contain hair and flesh, it in fact contains the entirety of all
the infinite amount of stuffs (a portion of everything). But how is this
possible?
d. The Divisibility of “Stuffs”
To understand how it is possible for there to be a portion of everything
in everything, it is necessary to develop Anaxagoras’ contention that stuff is
infinitely divisible. In practical terms, this can be explained by continuing
with the example of the rice kernel. For Anaxagoras, if one were to begin
dividing it into smaller and smaller portions there would be no point at which
the rice would no longer exist. Each infinitesimally small piece could be
divided into another, and each piece would continue to contain rice, as well as
hair, flesh and a portion of everything else. Prior to Anaxagoras, Zeno, a disciple of
Parmenides, argued against the notion that matter could be divided at all, let
alone infinitely. Apparently, Zeno had about forty reductio ad absurdum attacks on
pluralism, four of which are known to us. For our purposes, it is not necessary
to delve into these arguments, but a key assumption that arises from Zeno is
the contention that a plurality of things would make the notion of magnitude
meaningless. For Zeno, if an infinite division of things were possible then the
following paradox would arise. The divisions would conceivably be so small that
they would have no magnitude at all. At the same time, things would have to be
considered infinitely large in order to be able to be infinitely divided. While
the scholarly evidence is not conclusive, it seems quite possible that
Anaxagoras was replying to Zeno as he developed his notion of infinite
divisibility.
As the following fragment indicates, Anaxagoras did not consider the
consequence that Zeno presented to be problematic: “For of the small there is
no smallest, but always a smaller (for what is cannot not be). But also of the
large there is always a larger, and it is equal in amount to the small. But in
relation to itself, each is both large and small” (frag. 3). According to some
interpreters, what is remarkable about this fragment, and others similar to it,
is that it indicates the extent to which Anaxagoras grasped the notion of
infinity. As W.K.C. Guthrie points out, “Anaxagoras’ reply shows an
understanding of the meaning of infinity which no Greek before him had
attained: things are indeed infinite in quantity and at the same time
infinitely small, but they can go on becoming smaller to infinity without
thereby becoming mere points without magnitude” (289). Other interpretations
are somewhat less charitable toward Anaxagoras’ grasp of infinity, however, and
point out that he may not have been conceptualizing about the notion of
mathematical infinity when speaking about divisibility.
In any case, as strange as it may appear to modern eyes, Anaxagoras’
unique and subtle theory accomplished what it set out to do. It satisfied the
Parmenidian demand that nothing can come into or out of being and it accounted
for the plurality and change that constitutes our world of experience. A
difficult question remains for Anaxagoras’ theory, however.
e. Why is Something What It Is?
If, according to Anaxagoras, everything contains a portion of
everything, then what makes something (rice, for instance) what it is?
Anaxagoras does not provide a clear response to this question, but an answer is
alluded to in his claim that “each single thing is and was most plainly those
things of which it contains most.” (frag. 12) Presumably, this can be taken to
mean that each constituent of matter also has a part of matter that is predominant
in it. Commentators from Aristotle onward have struggled to make sense of this
notion, but it is perhaps Guthrie’s interpretation that is most helpful:
“Everything contains a portion of everything else, and a large piece of
something contains as many portions as a small piece of it, though they differ
in size; but every substance does not
contain all the infinite number of substances in equal proportions” (291). As such, a substance like rice,
while containing everything, contains a higher proportion of white, hardness,
etc. than a substance like wood. Simply stated, rice contains more stuff that
makes it rice than wood or any other substance. Presumably, rice also contains
higher proportions of flesh and hair than wood does. This would explain why,
from Anaxagoras’ perspective, an animal can become nourished by rice by not by
wood.
Anaxagoras’ theory of nature is quite innovative and complex, but
unfortunately his fragments do not provide us with very many details as to how
things work on a micro level. He does, however, provide us with a macro level
explanation for the origins of the world as we experience it. It is to his
cosmogony that we now turn our attention.
3. The Origins of the Cosmos
Anaxagoras’ theory of the origins of the world is reminiscent of the
cosmogonies that had been previously developed in the Ionion tradition,
particularly through Anaximenes and Anaximander. The traditional theories generally depict an
original unity which begins to become separated off into a series of opposites.
Anaxagoras maintained many of the key elements of these theories, however he
also updated these cosmogonies, most notably through the introduction of a
causal agent (Mind or nous)
that is the initiator of the origination process.
Prior to the beginning of world as we know it everything was combined
together in such a unified manner that there were no qualities or individual
substances that could be discerned. “All things were together, unlimited in
both amount and smallness.” (frag. 1) As such, reality was like the Parmenidian
whole, except this whole contained all the primary matters or “seeds,” which
are represented in the following passages through a series of opposites:
But before these things separated off, when [or, since] all things were
together, not even any color was manifest, for the mixture of all things
prevented it—the wet and the dry, the hot and the cold, the bright and the
dark, there being also much earth in the mixture and seeds unlimited in amount,
in no way like one another. For none of the other things are alike either, the
one to the other. Since this is so, it is necessary to suppose that all things
were in the whole. (frag. 4b) The things in the single cosmos are not separate from one another,
nor are they split apart with an axe, either the hot from the cold or the cold
from the hot (frag. 8).
At some point, the unity is spurred into a vortex motion at a force and
a speed “of nothing now found among humans, but altogether many times as fast”
(frag. 9). This motion begins the separation and it is “air and aither” that
are the first constituents of matter to become distinct. Again, this is not to
be seen in Empedoclean terms to indicate that air and ether are primary
elements They are simply a part of the infinite constituents of matter
represented by the phrase “mixture and seeds.” As the air and ether became
separated off, all other elements become manifest in this mixture as well:
“From these things as they are being separated off, earth is being compounded;
for water is being separated off out of the clouds, earth out of water, and out
of the earthy stones are being compounded by the cold, and these [i.e., stones]
move further out than the water” (frag. 16).
Therefore, the origin of the world is depicted through this process of
motion and separation from the unified mixture. As mentioned above, in
answering the “how” of cosmogony, Anaxagoras is fairly traditional in his
theory. In proposing an initiator or causal explanation for the origins of the
process, however, Anaxagoras separates himself from his predecessors.
4. Mind (nous)
a. The Role of Mind
According to Anaxagoras, the agent responsible for the rotation and
separation of the primordial mixture is Mind or nous: “And when Mind began to cause
motion, separating off proceeded to occur from all that was moved, and all that
Mind moved was separated apart, and as things were being moved and separated
apart, the rotation caused much more separating apart to occur” (fr. 13). As is
previously mentioned, it is rather significant that Anaxagoras postulates an
explanation for the movement of the cosmos, something that prior cosmogonies
did not provide. But how is this explanation to be understood? From the passage
above, one may infer that Mind serves simply as the initial cause for the
motion, and once the rotation is occurring, the momentum sets everything else
into place. In this instance it is tempting to assign a rather deistic function
to Mind. In other passages, however, Mind is depicted as “ruling” the rotation
and setting everything in order as well as having supreme power and knowledge
of all things (see fr. 12 and Simplicius’ Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, 495.20). In this case it
is tempting to characterize Mind in theistic terms. Both of these temptations
should be avoided, for Anaxagoras remained fully naturalistic in his
philosophy. In fact, the uniqueness of Anaxagoras is that he proposed a
rationalistic governing principle that remained free from the mythical or
theological characteristics of prior cosmogonies. His philosophical successors,
particularly Socrates, Plato and Aristotle, are very excited to find in
Anaxagoras a unifying cosmic principle which does not allude to the whims of
the gods. They hope to find in him an extension of this principle into a
purpose-driven explanation for the universe. Alas, they are all disappointed
that Anaxagoras makes no attempt to develop his theory of Mind in such a way.
What Socrates, Plato and Aristotle were hoping to discover in Anaxagoras
was not simply an account of how the cosmos originated (an efficient cause),
but an explanation for why and for what purpose the cosmos was initiated (a
final cause). Their initial excitement about his theory is replaced by
disillusionment in the fact that Anaxagoras does not venture beyond mechanistic
explanatory principles and offer an account for how Mind has ordered everything
for the best. For example, in the Phaedo,
Socrates discusses how he followed Anaxagoras’ argument with great joy, and
thought that he had found, “a teacher about the cause of things after my own
heart” (97d). Socrates’ joy is rather short-lived: “This wonderful hope was
dashed as I went on reading and saw that the man made no use of Mind, nor gave
it any responsibility for the management of things, but mentioned as causes air
and ether and water and many other strange things” (98b). Similarly, Aristotle
calls Anaxagoras a sober and original thinker, yet chastises him for using Mind
as a deus ex machina to
account for the creation of the world: “When he cannot explain why something is
necessarily as it is, he drags in Mind, but otherwise hew will use anything
rather than Mind to explain a particular phenomenon” (Metaphysics, 985a18). Despite the fact
that Anaxagoras did not pursue matters as far as his teleologically-minded
successors would have liked, his theory of Mind served as an impetus toward the
development of cosmological systems that speculated on final causes. On the
flip side, Anaxagoras’ lack of conjecture into the non-mechanistic forces in
the world also served as an inspiration to the more materialistic cosmological
systems that followed.
b. The Nature of Mind
Thus far, we have examined the role of Mind in the development of the
world. But what exactly is Mind, according to Anaxagoras? Based on the evidence
in the fragments, this is a rather difficult question to answer, for Mind
appears to have contradictory properties. In one small fragment, for example,
Anaxagoras claims that mind is the sole exception to the principle that there
is a portion of everything in everything, yet this claim is immediately
followed by the counter claim, “but Mind is in some things too” (frag. 11).
Elsewhere, Anaxagoras emphasizes the autonomy and separateness of Mind:
The rest have a portion of everything, but Mind is unlimited and
self-ruled and is mixed with no thing, but is alone and by itself. For if it
were not by itself but were mixed with something else, it would have a share of
all things, if it were mixed with anything. For in everything there is a
portion of everything, as I have said before. And the things mixed together
with it would hinder it so that it would rule no thing in the same way as it
does being alone and by itself. For it is the finest of all things and the
purest, and it has all judgment about everything and the greatest power. (frag.
12)
He goes on to say, however, that Mind “is very much even now where all
other things are too, in the surrounding multitude and in things that have come
together in the process of separating and in things that have separated off”
(frag. 14).
Most commentators maintain that Anaxagoras is committed to a dualism of some sort with
his theory of Mind. But his Mind/matter dualism is such that both constituents
appear to be corporeal in nature. Mind is material, but it is distinguished
from the rest of matter in that it is finer, purer and it appears to act
freely. This theory is best understood by considering Anaxagoras’ contention
that plants possess minds. It is the mind of a plant which enables it to seek
nourishment and grow, but this dynamic agent in a plant is not distinct from
the plant itself. This would have been a common biological view for the time,
but where Anaxagoras is novel is that he extends the workings of “mind” at the
level of plants and animals into a cosmic principle which governs all things.
The Mind of the cosmos is a dynamic governing principle which is immanent to
the entire natural system while still maintaining its transcendental
determining power. From Anaxagoras’ perspective it appears to be a principle
which is both natural and divine.
5. Other Theories
Anaxagoras’ theory of things and his postulation of Mind as a cosmic
principle are the most important and unique aspects of his philosophy. A few
other theories are worth mentioning, though it should be pointed out that many
of them are probably not original and our primary knowledge of these views
arises from second-hand sources.
As a natural scientist and philosopher of his day, Anaxagoras would have
been particularly concerned with the subjects of astronomy and meteorology and
he made some significant contributions in these areas. It was mentioned above
that his outlook on the heavenly bodies played a part in his condemnation in Athens. His beliefs about
the earth, moon and sun are clearly articulated in the following lengthy quote
from Hippolytus, a source from the late second century CE:
The earth [according to Anaxagoras] is flat in shape. It stays up
because of its size, because there is no void, and because the air, which is
very resistant, supports the earth, which rests on it. Now we turn to the
liquids on the earth: The sea existed all along, but the water in it became the
way it is because it suffered evaporation, and it is also added to from the
rivers which flow into it. Rivers originate from rains and also from
subterranean water; for the earth is hollow and has water in its hollows. The Nile rises in the summer because water is carried down
into it from the snow in the north.The sun, the moon, and all the heavenly
bodies are red-hot stones which have been snatched up by the rotation of the
aether. Below the heavenly bodies there exist certain bodies which revolve
along with the sun and the moon and are invisible….The moon is below the sun,
closer to us. The sun is larger than the Peloponnesus.
The moon does not shine with its own light, but receives its light from the
sun…. Eclipses of the moon occur when the earth cuts off the light, and
sometimes when the bodies below the moon cut off the light. Eclipses of the sun
take place at new moon, when the moon cuts off the light…. Anaxagoras was the
first to describe the circumstances under which eclipses occur and the way
light is reflected by the moon. He said that the moon is made of earth and has
plains and gullies on it. The Milky Way is the light of those stars which are
not lit up by the sun. (A Refutation of All
Heresies, 1, epitome, 3)
A key advantage of Anaxagoras’ belief that the heavenly bodies were
simply stone masses was that it enabled him to provide an account of meteorites
as bodies that occasionally become dislodged from the cosmic vortex and plummet
to earth. Plutarch attests that Anaxagoras was credited with predicting the
fall of a meteorite in 467 BCE, but it is unclear from the historical
attestations whether Anaxagoras’ theory predated or was prompted by the event.
Along with his contributions in Astronomy and Meteorology, Anaxagoras
proposed a theory of sensation that works on the principle of difference. The
assumption behind Anaxagoras’ theory is that there is some sort of qualitative
change that occurs with any sensation or perception. When a cold hand touches a
hot object the agent will only experience the sensation of heat because her hand
is cold and the hot object has brought about some sort of change. Therefore, in
order for this change (the sensation) to occur, it is necessary that unlike
things interact with each other, i.e., hot with cold, light with dark. If like
things interact—hot with hot, for example—then no change occurs and there is no
sensation. Perception works the same way as our sense of touch. Humans are able
to see better during the daytime because our eyes are generally dark.
Furthermore, perception works the same way as touch for Anaxagoras in that
there is a physical interaction with the perceiver and the object perceived.
Since a sensation requires an encounter with an opposite, Anaxagoras also
maintained that every sensory act is accompanied by some sort of irritation. As
Theophrastus notes, “Anaxagoras comes to this conclusion because bright colors
are excessively loud noises are irritating, and it is impossible to bear them
very long” (On Sense Perception,
27). Anaxagoras theory of sensation and perception is in direct opposition to
Empedocles who maintained that perception could be accounted for by an action
between like objects.
A couple of final speculations that are worth mentioning pertain to the
science of biology. It has already been noted that Anaxagoras believes plants
to have minds along with animals and humans. What places humans in a higher
category of intelligence, however, is the fact that we were equipped with
hands, for it is through these unique instruments that we are able to handle
and manipulate objects. Finally, Anaxagoras proposed an hypothesis on how the
sex of an infant is determined. If the sperm comes from the right testicle it
will attach itself to the right side of the womb and the baby will be a male.
If the sperm comes from the left testicle it will attach itself to the left
side of the womb and the baby will be a female.
6. References and Further Reading
- Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. New York, NY: Routledge, 1996.
- Furley, David. Anaxagoras, “Plato and Naming of Parts.” Presocratic Philosophy. Eds. Victor Caston and Daniel W. Graham. Burlington VT: Ashgate Publishing Limited, 2002. 119-126.
- Gershenson, Daniel E. and Greenberg, Daniel A. Anaxagoras and the Birth of Physics. New York: Blaisdell Publishing Company, 1964. [It should be pointed out that scholars have been rather critical of this work, but it is a rather helpful reference for sources on Anaxagoras.]
- Graham, Daniel, “The Postulates of Anaxagoras”, Apeiron 27 (1994), pp.77-121.
- Guthrie, W.K.C. A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965.
- Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E. and Schofield, M. The Presocratic Philosophers. 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
- McKirahan, Richard D. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994.
- Schofield, Malcolm. An Essay on Anaxagoras. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
- Sider, David. The Fragments of Anaxagoras. 2nd ed. revised. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, 2005
- Taylor, C.C.W. “Anaxagoras and the Atomists.” From the Beginning to Plato: Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. I. Ed. C.C.W. Taylor. New York, NY: Routledge, 1997. 208-243.
Author Information
Michael PatziaEmail: michael.patzia@lmu.edu
Central College
U. S. A.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário