GORGIAS (487 - 376 a.C.)
It was a Pre-Socratic Greek philosopher,
orator and rhetorician from Sicily.
Along with Protagoras, he was one of the major figures in the first
generation of Sophists.
Both Plato and Aristotle criticized Gorgias
severely, labelling him as a mere sophist (in the derogatory sense of "sophistry")
whose primary goal was to make money by appearing wise and clever, and
not a true philosopher. However, he was undeniably highly influential
and, in bringing his rhetorical innovations from his native Sicily
to Athens and Attica,
he also contributed to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the
language of literary prose.
Life
Gorgias (pronounced GOR-jas) was born
around 487 B.C. (or possibly 483 B.C.) in Leontini, a Greek colony in Sicily. His
father was named Charmantides, and he had at least two siblings, a
brother named Herodicus and a (unnamed) sister. In his youth, he may
have been a pupil of Empedocles, although he would only have been a few years
younger. He was familiar with the works of Zeno of Elea and used his paradoxes (especially the
so-called "arguments against motion") in his own work.
He was already about sixty when he was sent in 427
B.C. to Athens
by his fellow-citizens at the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian
protection against the aggression of the neighbouring Syracusans. On
completing his mission, he subsequently settled in Athens, probably due to the enormous
popularity of his style of oratory and the profits he could make
from his performances and rhetoric classes.
Like other Sophists, he was an itinerant, practising in various cities and giving public
exhibitions of his rhetorical skill at the great pan-Hellenic centers of Olympia
and Delphi (including inviting questions from the audience and giving impromptu
replies), and charged substantial fees for his instruction and
performances. His florid, rhyming style seemed to almost hypnotize
his audiences, and his powers of persuasion were legendary.
Among his distinguished students in Athens were
Isocrates (436 - 338 B.C., one of the greatest and most influential orators
of his time), Critias (460 - 403 B.C., a leading member of the so-called
Thirty Tyrants of Athens), Alcibiades (c. 450 - 404 B.C., a
prominent Athenian statesman, orator and general), Thucydides (c.
460 - 395 B.C., an important historian), Agathon (c. 448 - 400 B.C., a
popular tragic poet) and Pericles (c. 495 - 429 B.C., a prominent and
influential statesman, orator and general of Athens).
Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be over one
hundred years old, before dying at Larissa in Thessaly in about 375 B.C. or 376 B.C. He had accumulated
considerable wealth by the time of his death, enough to commission a gold
statue of himself for a public temple.
Work
Gorgias transplanted rhetoric from his native Sicily to Athens
and Attica, and in the process contributed to
the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose.
He ushered in rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation
and the introduction of paradoxes and paradoxical expression, for
which he has been labelled the "father of sophistry". His
rhetorical works (including the "Encomium of Helen", "Defence
of Palamedes" and "Epitaphios") come down
to us via a work entitled "Technai", a manual of
rhetorical instruction.
Unlike other Sophists like Protagoras, Gorgias did not profess to teach arete
(or virtue), believing that there was no absolute form of virtue but
that it was relative to each situation. He believed that rhetoric
was the king of all other sciences, since it was capable of persuading
any course of action. Thus, much of the debate over the nature and value
of rhetoric, began with Gorgias. Plato (one of Gorgias’ greatest critics) was speaking in direct
opposition to Gorgias, when he argued that rhetoric gives the ignorant
the power to seem more knowledgeable than an expert to a group, and that
Gorgias was merely an orator who entertains his audience with his eloquent
words while believing that it is unnecessary to learn the truth
about actual matters.
A lost work, "On Nature" or "On
Non-Existence", was one of Gorgias few essays into Metaphysics. It is available to us only in paraphrases
from Sextus Empiricus (2nd or 3rd Century A.D.) and others, and it is
generally skeptical in outlook, intended both as a refutation and
as a parody of the Eleatic School, and particularly of Parmenides. It is usually presented as a three-point
argument: 1) nothing exists; 2) even if something exists, nothing can be
known about it; and 3) even if something can be known about it,
knowledge about it can't be communicated to others. His point was to
prove that it is just as easy to demonstrate that being is one,
unchanging and timeless as it is to prove that being has no existence at
all.
Gorgias (483—375 B.C.E.)
Gorgias was a Sicilian philosopher, orator, and rhetorician. He is
considered by many scholars to be one of the founders of sophism, a movement
traditionally associated with philosophy, that emphasizes the practical application
of rhetoric toward civic and political life. The sophists were itinerant
teachers who accepted fees in return for instruction in oratory and rhetoric,
and many claimed they could teach anything and its opposite (thesis and
antithesis). Another aspect of their method was the ability to make the weaker
argument the stronger. The term sophist in
classical Greek was a general appellation denoting a "wise man." They
were important figures in Greece
in the 4th and 5th centuries, and their social success was great. Plato was the first to
use the term rhêtorikê, while
the sophists termed their "art" logos
. Nevertheless, Gorgias is commonly associated with the development
of rhetoric in classical Greece.
The democratic process in Athens
supplied the need for instruction in both rhetoric and philosophy.
Despite efforts by G.W.F Hegel and George Grote toward rehabilitating the
reputations of Gorgias and the other sophists in the 19th century, the sophists
still had a foul reputation well into the 20th century (as evidenced by the
pejorative term "sophistry"). In 1930, French philosopher Jacques
Maritain remarked "[s]ophistry is not a system of ideas, but a vicious
attitude of the mind;" the sophists "came to consider as the most
desirable form of knowledge the art of refuting and disproving by skillful
arguments" (32-33). In recent years, however, modernists and
post-structuralists have found great value in the philosophy of Gorgias,
especially his theories on truth and language.
1. Life and Works
Gorgias (483-375 B.C.E.) came to Greece
from Leontini in Sicily.
Little is known of his life before he arrived in Athens
in 427 B.C.E. as a political ambassador seeking military assistance against Syracuse, a city-state in Sicily. He delivered a series of speeches
that dazzled the Athenian audiences and won him fame and admiration. Upon
completion of his mission, he traveled throughout Greece as a teacher of rhetoric and
as an orator, and according to Aristotle, spoke at the Panhellenic festivals (Art of Rhetoric 1414b29). He was a student of Empedocles, and
according to Quintilian and others, was the teacher of Isocrates. Plato
identifies Meno (Meno 76Aff)
among the students of Gorgias, and he may have been one of Aspasia's
instructors as well. Many of the sophists set up schools and charged fees in
return for instruction in rhetoric, and Gorgias was no exception. Philostratus
(Lives of the Sophists I 9, I)
tells us that Gorgias began the practice of extemporaneous oratory, and that he
had the boldness to say "'suggest a subject' ...he was the first to
proclaim himself willing to take the chance, showing apparently that he knew
everything and would trust the moment to speak on any subject." He died at
the age of 108 at Larissa in Thessaly.
Four works are attributed to Gorgias: On
the Nonexistent or On Nature,
the Apology of Palamedes, the Encomium on Helen, and the Epitaphios or Athenian Funeral Oration. The original text of On Nature has been lost, and survives
only in two different paraphrases, one in Sextus Empiricus' Against the Professors and another in an
anonymous work entitled Melissus,
Xenophanes, Gorgias. There are two different manuscripts of Palamedes and Helen (the Cripps and Palatine
versions), one slightly different than the other. Legal historians consider the
Defense of Palamedes to be an
important contribution to dicanic [explanatory] argumentation, and some
cultural historians believe the Epitaphios was
used as a stylistic and genre source for Plato's Menexenus (Cosigny 2). Gorgias' rhyming style is highly
poetic, and he viewed the orator as an individual leading a kind of group
incantation. He employs metaphor and figurative expressions to illustrate his
assertions, and even uses humor as one instrument of refutation. The term macrologia (using more words than
necessary in an effort to appear eloquent) is sometimes used to describe his
oratorical technique (Kennedy 63).
2. Philosophy
Any student of Gorgias must immediately mark the distinction between his
philosophy as expressed by Plato in the dialogue Gorgias (see below) and his philosophy found within the
three works: On the Nonexistent,
the Apology of Palamedes, and
the Encomium on Helen.
a. Ontology & Epistemology
Nowhere is Gorgias' sophistical love of paradox more evident than in the
short treatise On the Nonexistent or
On Nature. The subject of this
work is ontological (concerning nature of being), but it also deals with
language and epistemology (the study of the nature and limitations of knowledge). In addition to
this, it can be understood as an exercise in sophistical rhetoric; Gorgias
tackles an argument that is seemingly impossible to refute, namely that, after
considering our world, we must come to the conclusion that "things
exist." His powerful argument to the contrary proves his abilities as a
master of oratory, and some believe the text was used as an advertisement of
his credentials.
Gorgias begins his argument by presenting a logical contradiction,
"if the nonexistent exists, it will both exist and not exist at the same
time" (B3.67) (a violation of the principle of non-contradiction). He then
denies that existence (to on)
itself exists, for if it exists, it is either eternal or generated. If it is
eternal, it has no beginning, and is therefore without limit. If it is without
limit, it is "nowhere" (B3.69), and hence does not exist. And if
existence is generated, it must come from something, and that something is
existence, which is another contradiction. Likewise, nonexistence (to mê on) cannot produce anything
(B3.71). The sophist then explains that existence can neither be
"one" (hen) or
"many" (polla), since
if it were one, it would be divisible, and therefore not one. If it were many,
it would be a "composite of separate entities" (B3.74) and no longer
the thing known as existence.
Gorgias then turns his attention to what is knowable and comprehensible.
He remarks, "if things considered [imagined or thought] in the mind are
not existent, the existent is not considered" (B3.77), that is to say,
existence is incomprehensible. This supposition is backed up by the fact that
one can imagine chariots racing in the sea, but that does not make such a thing
happen. The operation of the mind (intellection) is fundamentally distinct from
what happens in the real world; "the existent is not an object of
consideration and is not apprehended" (B3.82). It is helpful to think of
apprehension here in Aristotelian terms, as simple
apprehension, the first operation of reasoning (logic) in which the
intellect "grasps" or "apprehends" something. Simple
apprehension happens when the mind first forms a concept of something in the
world, and is anterior to judgment.
Finally, Gorgias proclaims that even if existence could be apprehended,
"it would be incapable of being conveyed to another" (B3.83). This is
because what we reveal to another is not an external substance, but is merely logos (from the Greek verb lego, "to say"--see below). Logos is not "substances and
existing things" (B3.84). External reality becomes the revealer of logos (B3.85); while we can know logos, we cannot apprehend things
directly. The color white, for instance, goes from a property of a thing, to a
mental representation, and the representation is different than the thing
itself. In its summation, this nihilistic argument becomes a
"trilemma":
i. Nothing
exists
ii. Even if existence exists, it cannot be known
iii. Even if it could be known, it cannot be communicated.
ii. Even if existence exists, it cannot be known
iii. Even if it could be known, it cannot be communicated.
This argument has led some to label Gorgias as either an ontological
skeptic or a nihilist (one who believes nothing exists, or that the world is
incomprehensible, and that the concept of truth is fictitious). But it can also
be interpreted as an assertion that it is logos
and logos alone
which is the proper object of our inquiries, since it is the only thing we can
really know. On Nature is sometimes seen as a
refutation of pre-Socratic essentialist philosophy (McComiskey 37).
b. Rhetorical Theory
Most of what we know concerning Gorgias' views on rhetoric comes from
the Encomium. This work can be
understood as a sophistical effort to rehabilitate the reputation of Helen of
Troy. In it, Gorgias attempts to take the weaker argument and make it the stronger
one, by arguing for a position contrary to well-established opinion: in this
case, the opinion that Helen was to blame for the Trojan War. Gorgias argues
that Helen succumbed either to (a) physical force (Paris' abduction), (b) love (eros), or (c) verbal persuasion (logos), and in any instance, she cannot
be blamed for her actions. According to Gorgias, logos is a powerful force that can be used nefariously to
convince people to do things against their own interests. It can take the form
of poetry (metrical language), divine incantations, or oratory. Logos is described as a "powerful
lord" (B11.8) and "[t]he effect of speech upon the condition of the
soul is comparable to the power of drugs over the nurture of bodies"
(B11.14). This should be contrasted with the view of Isocrates that logos is a "chief" or
"commander" (Nicoles 5-9).
The difference here is subtle, but Gorgias' dynastic
concept of logos clearly
turns it into a despotic overlord, while Isocrates' "commander" is a
leader with delegated authority, an individual who fights along side his
troops.
Examples of persuasive speech, according to Gorgias, are the
"conflicts among the philosophers’ arguments in which the swiftness of
demonstration and judgment make the belief in any opinion changeable"
(B11.13). This is similar to the assertion of Sextus Empiricus that equally
convincing arguments can be formed against, or in favor of, any subject.
Gorgias may have believed in a relative notion of truth that was contingent
upon a particular kairos (an
opportune moment or "opening"), that is to say, truth can only be
found within a given moment. He seems to reject the idea of truth as a
philosophically universal principle, and thus comes into conflict with Plato
and Aristotle. Nevertheless, the rhetor (orator) is ethically obligated to
avoid deception, and it is "the duty of the same man both to declare what
he should rightly and to refute what has been spoken falsely" (B11.2).
Ultimately, Gorgias’ opinion concerning truth is difficult to ascertain, but
from his writings, we can conclude that he was more concerned with rhetorical
argument than the truth of any given proposition or assertion.
In the epideictic speech Defense of
Palamedes, Gorgias uses a mythical narrator (Palamedes) to further
illustrate his rhetorical technique and philosophy. In the Odyssey, Palamedes
was responsible for revealing Odysseus' "madness" as a fiction, an
act for which the latter never forgave him. Ultimately, Palamedes was executed
for treason, after Odysseus accused him of conspiring with the Trojans. Gorgias
focuses on the invention of arguments (topoi)
necessary to exonerate Palamedes within the setting of a fictional trial, all
of which depend upon probability. Palamedes
could not have committed treason with a foreign power since he speaks no
language other than Greek (B11a.6-7), and no Greek desires social power among
barbarians (B11a.13). In the second example, we see that topoi "embody the values of the
community, in the sense that they comprise what the community considers
important" (Cosigny 84). A fundamental difference between the topoi found within Aristotle's Art of Rhetoric and Gorgias' topoi is that Aristotle's are
"acontextual, while Gorgias places his in the narrative context of the
Palamedes myth" (McComiskey 49). Therefore, there is a direct relationship
between kairos and invention.
Gorgias rejects the use of pathos (emotional
appeal) in his Defense, with
the assertion that "among you, who are the foremost of the Greeks ...there
is no need to persuade such ones as you with the aid of friends and sorrowful
prayers and lamentations" (B11a.33). He prefers to use ethos (ethical appeal, or arguments from
character) and logos, as his
instruments of persuasion.
3. Critics
Gorgias' most famous critic is Plato. In the dialogue Gorgias, Plato (through his mentor
Socrates) expresses his contempt for sophistical rhetoric; all rhetoric is
"a phantom of a branch of statesmanship (463d) ...a kind of flattery
...that is contemptible," because its aim is simply pleasure rather than
the welfare of the public. Nor can rhetoric be considered an art (technê), since it is irrational (465a).
The end result of rhetoric is a cosmetic alteration of language that conceals
truth and falsity (465b). Furthermore, rhetoric is "designed to produce
conviction, but not educate people, about matters of right or wrong (455a). The
character of Gorgias in the dialogue is forced to admit that his
"art" deals with opinion (doxa)
rather than knowledge (epistemê);
that its intention is to persuade rather than to instruct, and that rhetoric
deals with language without regard to content. Gorgias is portrayed as a man
with an ambivalent attitude towards truth, a relativist, who boldly asserts
that it does not matter if one truly has knowledge of any given subject, only
that he is perceived by others
to have knowledge, and that "[r]hetoric is the only area of expertise you
need to learn. You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the
professionals!" (459c).
There are a number of explanations for Plato's antipathy towards
sophistic rhetoric. The first is simply philosophical; Plato was not a
relativist, nor did he believe rhetoric had a pedagogical value. But there is
also a political element to be considered. Bruce McComiskey points out that
Plato believed in an "oligarchic government" for Athens, while many of the sophists
"favored the Athenian Democracy the way it was" (20). It is important
to point out that during Gorgias' lifetime, both Leontini and Athens were democratic city states and a
loose alliance existed between the two. On a more practical level, the Greek
city states also served as a market for those who would sell instruction in rhetoric.
Aristotle dismisses Gorgias as a "frigid" stylist who
indulges in excessive use of compound words such as
"begging-poet-flatterers" and "foresworn and well-sworn" (Art of Rhetoric 1405b34). He also faults
Gorgias for overly poetic language (1406b4), and we can see examples of this in
Gorgias' description of logos as
a great dynast or lord (B11.8) and as a "drug" (B11.14). The sophist
compares orators to "frogs croaking in water"(B3.30), and
philosophers to the "suitors of Penelope" (B3.29).
Despite efforts by G.W.F Hegel and George Grote toward rehabilitating the
reputations of Gorgias and the other sophists in the 19th century, the sophists
still had a foul reputation well into the 20th century (as evidenced by the
pejorative term "sophistry"). In 1930, French philosopher Jacques
Maritain remarked "[s]ophistry is not a system of ideas, but a vicious
attitude of the mind;" the sophists "came to consider as the most
desirable form of knowledge the art of refuting and disproving by skillful
arguments" (32-33). In recent years, however, modernists and
post-structuralists have found great value in the philosophy of Gorgias,
especially his theories on truth and language.
6. References and Further Reading
a. Primary sources
- Aristophanes. Clouds. Intro. and trans. by Carol Poster. In Aristophanes 3, ed. David Slavitt and Palmer Bovie. Philadelphia PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1999: 85-192.
- Diels, Hermann. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Rev. Walther Kranz. Berlin: Weidmann, 1972-1973.
- Diogenes Laertius. Lives Of Eminent Philosophers. Trans. R. D. Hicks. 2 vols. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1959.
- Plato. Plato II: Laches, Protagoras, Meno, Euthydemus. Trans. W. R. M. Lamb. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1967.
- Plato. Plato VII: Theaetetus, Sophist. Trans. H. N. Fowler. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1925.
- Sextus Empiricus. Sextus Empiricus. Trans. R. G. Bury. 4 vols. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1953-59.
- Sprague, Rosamund Kent, ed. The Older Sophists: A Complete Translation by Several Hands. Columbia SC: University of South Carolina Press, 1972.
b. Secondary sources
- Guthrie, W. K. C. The Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971
- de Romilly, Jaqueline. The Great Sophists In Periclean Athens. Trans. Janet Lloyd. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1992.
- Kennedy, George. The Art Of Persuasion In Greece. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963.
- Kerferd, G. B. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
- Rankin, H. D. Sophists, Socratics & Cynics. London: Croom Helm, 1983.
- Schiappa, Edward. Protagoras and Logos. Columbia S.C.: University of South Carolina Press 1991.
Author Information
Carol PosterEmail: cposter@english.fsu.edu
Florida State University
U. S. A.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário